16
Capturing movement

A videomusical approach sourced in the natural environment

Myriam Boucher

Composing with visual and aural matter

Sky, birds, clouds, forest, sea, mountains. The natural environment presents an invaluable material world with and within which we maintain a complex relationship. In Nature, the writer Jeffrey Kastner explains:

In my videomusical work, I capture movement from matter as it evolves in its natural setting. Both sounds and images are recorded at the same time. Typically, I will choose a fixed camera/microphone position in order to capture the movement of a particular sound or image. If I decide to move the camera/microphone then it will be with the intention to present a precise point of view and perspective. This perspective will be chosen in order to construct a narrative.

Rather than approaching nature as a landscape, I am inspired by the physical experience of being present and immersed in the natural world, which consequently impacts on how I see and hear. I endeavour to perceive the world surrounding me in an active, participatory way and for this embodied knowledge to inform my work. This act of actively seeing and hearing within the natural world is followed by analysing and re-organising the movements I have captured and recorded in order to create videomusic.

In the studio, I edit these recordings to select aural and visual materials that speak to me with, for example, their gestural energy or textural qualities. In the compositional process, the number of recordings I choose to use vary greatly. This material leads me to integrate and create more material. The result is a mixture of field recordings, live footage, found footage, instrumental recordings with musicians, and/or synthesised sound and image.

The materials are arranged and transformed by digital manipulations. The purpose of these manipulations is not to conceal the original source, but to accentuate aural and visual movement nestled in colours, shapes and forms. Most of the recordings I select have a subtle tone, a specific grain, detailed lines, dynamic behaviour or interesting arrangements that I isolate and amplify. I edit sound and image to create a dialectic relationship between the two media. This dialogue is related to our experience of the physical world.

The main objective at this stage of my composing process is to transform movements into musical gestures and textures which will be used to define the videomusical discourse of the work.

I will define musical gesture more precisely further on, however in videomusic, a musical gesture is both aural and visual, and understood as a meaningful shaping of materials through time. The context in which this shaping is manifest will, I hope, lead to a meaningful experience of time and motion.

My purpose is not to document or to represent something, but to create meaning within the videomusical form where sound and image contribute equally. Meaning is constructed as a poetic form, built from mental images, metaphors and symbolism, generated by the very matter it is built with and how it unfolds in time.

In the following sections, I will present movement, musical gesture, texture and meaning as interrelated concepts that form the backbone of my practice. I will use my works Reflets (2015), Kabir Kouba (2016) and Vagues (2017)1 as relevant expressions of these ideas. They all use the movement of water.

Movement

A movement is a change of position, a form developing or changing in a given direction. This direction need not be linear and its perception is based on the recognition of change. Crucially, movement and rate of change are independent concepts.

In the natural environment, movement resides in the behaviour of the material itself. For example, waves of water, wind in the trees, flocks of birds or a raging tornado are both aural and visual elements in motion.

By its very nature, sound is a consequence of movement. The continuous sound of a waterfall, the unpredictable soundings of thunder or the crack of a driving golf ball are all examples of how the energy of movement is transduced into acoustic energy. Indeed, all sound implies movement of one kind or another.

Capturing water movement

My works Reflets, Kabir Kouba and Vagues are composed with the inherent musicality found in the movements of water:

Reflets is constructed from footage of water reflections recorded at the Canal Lachine (Montréal, Canada) by a rainy, windy and cloudy day (see Figure 16.1) (Video 16.1).

ifig0001.jpg

Figure 16.1 Footage from Canal Lachine (Montréal, Canada).

Figure 16.1 Footage from Canal Lachine (Montréal, Canada).

The water is constantly moving and flowing, creating a homogeneous movement that becomes hypnotising. Our attention is drawn to textures: colour changes, caustic lines and little waves caused by wind. The surrounding sound is loud, mainly composed of heavy wind and the noise of the city.

The aural and visual recordings of Kabir Kouba present a great variety of water flux coming from the Kabir Kouba Cliff and Waterfall crossed by the Saint-Charles River (Wendake, Canada) (Video 16.2). With its intersections, diversions and downstream flow, this stream presents various aural and visual movements, from the calmest to the most powerful (see Figure 16.2).

ifig0001.jpg

Figure 16.2 Footage from Kabir Kouba (Wendake Reserve, Canada).

Figure 16.2 Footage from Kabir Kouba (Wendake Reserve, Canada).

The materials used in Vagues contain movements recorded at Kabir Kouba (see Figure 16.2) and Lake Champlain (VT, USA – see Figure 16.3) (Video 16.3). This piece also includes visual directional movements, with clear beginnings and endings, like water splashes. Field recordings of water and environments relating to the sea, such as boats, birds, dinghies and the ambient noise of the harbour, are used. This larger variety of aural and visual movements used allowed me flexibility for the creation of musical gestures.

ifig0001.jpg

Figure 16.3 Footage from Lake Champlain (VT, USA).

Figure 16.3 Footage from Lake Champlain (VT, USA).

Musical gesture

The definition of musical gesture is a complex and largely intuitive undertaking. Most writings on musical gesture make the assumption that a gesture is a movement, a mutating energy or change in state that becomes marked as significant by an agent (Gritten and King 2006). This definition considers human gesture as “[a]ny energetic shaping through time, whether actual or implied, and whether intentional or unwitting” (Hatten 2006: 1). The energetic shaping must also be interpreted as meaningful in some way. A musical gesture expresses meaningful combinations of sound and movement (Godoy and Leman 2010: 3).

In Spectromorphology: Explaining Sound-Shapes, Denis Smalley develops this idea of energetic gesture by arguing that a gesture is an “energy-motion trajectory which excites the sounding body, creating spectromorphological life. From the viewpoint of both agent and watching listener, the musical gesture-process is tactile and visual as well as aural” (Smalley 1997: 111).

However, Hatten argues that gestures “translate into music as more than energetic through time, and more than the energy it takes a performer to produce sound” (Hatten 2006: 3). In music, energetic musical gestures are arranged into a musical discourse. This arrangement can be seen as a virtual environment “in which we can trace the presence of an animating force (implying an independent agent) by the constraints that weigh in on (deflect, deform, or resolve) otherwise freely motivated energetic movement” (Hatten 2006: 3).

According to Hatten, musical gestures can be motivated by several factors: indexical (dynamic, association by contiguity or connection), iconic (imagistic, association by the similarity of properties or structures), syntactic and symbolic (Hatten 2006: 3). It is the interaction of these motivations that makes the musical gesture so meaningful. Musical gesture, Hatten argues, conveys affective motion, emotion and intentionality by blending otherwise separate elements on a continuum of shape, drive and force.

Hatten and Smalley’s definitions are easily transposable to a context where the gesture is not only dependent or directly associated with sound, but also with image.

In traditional cinema, a visual gesture usually has a direct transcription in sound (Oliveira 2018). By exaggerating visual movement, musical cues and sound effects joined with objects create more life than their simple presence as figures in motion (Whalen 2004). The sound design in action movies is an example of this transcription of visual gesture into sound: punching, fight scene, flying Superhero, etc. Another example is mickey-mousing, a film technique that syncs the music to the actions seen (see The Band Concert 1935).

However, in videomusic, we observe that many other kinds of relations between sound and image are used. It is possible to find connections between gestures in sound and image that have multiple meanings and go beyond the simple mimicry of one by the other. As reported by Oliveira (2018), if an image has a meaning, sound may or may not support or increase that meaning by an aural musical gesture. On the other hand, sound can give meaning to an image that does not possess it intrinsically (such as a synthesised abstract object). The sound/image relation plays an important role in the organisation of the energy enacted by musical gestures (whether visual or aural). This relation, therefore, has a direct impact on how an audiovisual work is perceived and felt.

Gesture and sound/image relation

I work with the movement of natural elements to compose relational progressions of sounds and images as they intersect, clash, distend or collide through time. By editing and combining aural and visual movements, it is possible, for example, to create musical gestures consisting of a river flow followed by a splash, a stream intersecting a sea wave, or two water trajectories clashing together. The sound of those gestures may come from water or not. The intention behind the sound/image relation is to give a viewpoint and to complexify the stimulus presented. In a major way, sound/image relations will lead the intention behind the musical progression. As they do so, they create expectations, directionality, suspension, emphasis or restraint. Musical gestures carry intentionality. Their meaning intuitively emerges in the mind of a viewer-listener via her/his imagination. This meaning is constructed by the way the viewer-listener’s body responds to the energy deployed by the organisation of musical gestures.

In Kabir Kouba, moving images are edited to establish a dialogue between each other. Movements of the water cross each other, then they separate to meet again. Extracted from the footage, but constructed by image editing and understated synthesised images (see Figure 16.4), the visual composition is entirely joined with the sound. The idea was to compose the music from the image, using the visual composition as a musical score. Along with field recordings of water, synthesised sounds are used to support, increase and imitate visual movements in the flowing water.

Figure 16.4 Stills from Kabir Kouba.

Figure 16.4 Stills from Kabir Kouba.

The sound acts as an accentuator for visual elements, bringing directionality to the continuous movement of the images. Conversely, the sound is often an echo to the visual movements. Sound can evolve by itself for a while and then come back in symbiosis with the image. It is a composition of meeting points and counterpoints between visual and aural elements that move together or independently and evolve through a floating and ephemeral time. Visual gestures affect the musical path with a transference of meaning going from image to sound. At the same time, aural gestures affect how visual material is perceived.

Gesture and causality

The organisation of musical gestures refers to actions, evolution and transformations. It concerns the application of energy and its consequences (Oliveira 2018). It is a combination of intervention, direction and progression over time; “a chain of activity links a cause to a source” (Smalley 1997: 111).

Gesture, in Smalley’s theory, represents a fundamental approach to structuring electroacoustic music. A musical gesture is related to the notion of causality, “where one event seems to cause the onset of a successor, or alter a concurrent event in some way” (Smalley 1997: 118). It relates to the communicative and expressive potential as an “articulation of continuum” (Wishart 1996: 17).

A simple example is to throw a stone into a lake. This action changes the state of the water, which was calm, by suddenly causing a series of waves around the entry point of the stone. This causal link (launching a stone that causes waves) is important for understanding how movement becomes gesture, and how the organisation of musical gestures relates to changes in energy.

As mentioned by Oliveira (2018), some examples of movement sharply contradict this idea of gesture. This happens when there is a limited or non-existent change in energy. In such a case, both sound and image lose their gestures to become textural.

Texture and the absence of gesture

Texture intrinsically comes from movement. But unlike gesture, it presents static energy, a rest, with a non-defined causality (Oliveira 2018).

My work Reflets is composed of two superposed visual movements: waves and reflections of a bridge in the water. The images are transformed to present the fine lines created by the reflections and the waves. Their evolution is caused by wind variations and clouds passing above (see Figure 16.5). The visuals are always changing but do not give a clear directionality. The wind behaviour is used as a dynamic model for the music, which is composed of synthesisers and piano strings manipulations.

Figure 16.5 Stills from the three scenes of Reflets.

Figure 16.5 Stills from the three scenes of Reflets.

The movement found in this work induces an experience of stasis, because it is always changing in a similar manner. The music generally follows the same path. The absence of gesture in the image is reflected in the absence of gesture in the sound, except for the three visual cuts that are accentuated by a sonic musical gesture. The sound/image relationship is used to accentuate and draw attention to textures, while supporting a contemplative musical form.

Oliveira (2018) points out that in both sound and image, energy is a consequence of movement. It is in constant transformation. The interaction between energy and what causes its release is similar to the gestural interaction between sound and image (Oliveira 2018). One gesture may inflect or trigger another one, terminate or bifurcate a flux of images and sound or, when successful, compose a discourse of sound and visual information that carry meaning, however diffuse or personal. Energy may be maintained, accumulated or converted, localised or diffused (Oliveira 2018). Sound and image moving together are energy through gestures and textures, shaping our perception of time and creating an alternate audiovisual experience.

Meaning and imagination

Connotative and energetic meaning

I will discuss two kinds of meaning, as they relate to the natural environment: the connotative and the energetic. Similar types of meaning are discussed in Lehrer (2011) but my approach to the subject is slightly different – it goes beyond the purely musical aspect (in the conventional sense which mainly concerns rhythm and harmony) and does not directly address neuroscience studies.

The relationship between connotative and energetic meaning will help distinguish the codependence of narrative and abstraction, and will, in time compose a meta-narrative form of story-telling. In this meta-narrative form, the implicit meaning is provided by both the matter-centric imagination and the energy deployed by the matter. Connoted and energetic meaning are intertwined to form an arc carrying several emotions, representations and feelings. These meaningful connections are understood from the subjective perspective of the viewer-listener. The intention of the composer is not to control this. Implicitly or explicitly, the viewer-listener will make sense of these meanings.

The connotative meaning of a recognisable object includes the feelings and ideas that we may associate with that object. For example, a bird, a river or a tree usually refer to the real world of experiences. Our perception of the physical world is concerned by factors beyond the visual and aural recognition.

In Vagues, there is a short scene presenting a black frame and a seabird sound. A natural seabird transmits known sound, which is associated with the sea. A seabird is a real object within a range of physical shapes and colours. If a seabird is heard, most subjects will readily identify it and move on to explore other levels of meaning in the seabird. The subject will likely have personal experiences with seabirds, perhaps that of holidays spent by the sea or a passage on a ferry boat.

Moreover, the meaning depends on the relationship between all components of the work. It depends on the chain of sounds and images presented which will elevate the first impression of something else. In the context of Vagues, the seabird is obviously related to the water environment because various images of water are shown previously. According to this chain of relations, the bird may, for example, become a vector of freedom, alert or escape. Be that as it may, the cognitive relationship with the object has moved beyond physicality and stimulus. And the sense is thus established – it resides outside the object and inside experience, and of course, experience may vary from one individual to another.

Energetic meaning arises from abstraction and movement. It refers to colours, form, kinetic/morphologic characteristics, to the musical and its propulsive properties, and mostly, to the various relationships enacted by sounds and moving imagery. It emerges from the energy found in the aural and visual materials recorded, edited and manipulated.

Our brain is the screen

About moving imagery, the philosopher Gilles Deleuze affirms in an interview given in Les Cahiers du Cinéma (Bergala 1986) that “our brain is the screen – that is to say, ourselves”. I start from this statement to argue that our brain is the screen where the invented world – the work – unfolds. We don’t see its exterior envelope; we live it from the inside, immersed in it. This immersive experience unfolds when our brain accepts this self-referential organisation and signs a form of cognitive contract. We willfully abandon everyday reality to involve ourselves in fantasy, dreaming wide awake. On moving imagery, Thomas Zummer writes:

Any videomusic work proposes an invented place, the reality of which we, as viewer-listeners, contribute to defining. Through an informed acceptance of the artifices that make up that place, we construct meaning. The construction of meaning confronts our present experience of a work with the ensemble of our previous experiences of a similar aesthetic or cultural nature. The credibility of what is proposed depends on the coherence of the fictional universe we participated in defining. If only to ourselves, it must, ultimately, make sense.

But how does one create meaning with works mainly built from movements of natural matter? Likewise, where does meaning come from when there is an absence of explicit narrative? Intentionality, mental imaging, metaphors and symbolism are all part of the answer, and they are predominantly formed by each individual experience.

Intentionality

In his study Musical Intentionality: Between Objects and Meaning, Lee explores how intentionality structures the ways in which aspects of musical materiality relate to musical meaning. The author examines some of the basic structures of intentionality presented in Searle’s general theory (1983) and recalls that intentionality “denotes those aspects of conscious mental states that are directed at, are about, or represent states of affairs beyond themselves” (Lee 2016: 34). According to Lee, any “conscious mental state that has directedness – or ‘aboutness’ – to something beyond itself might be called an intentionalistic state” (Lee 2016: 34). Owing to the intrinsic subjectivity of mental representations, intentional contents and their objects are represented under unique aspects. On that point, Lee argues:

If we consider water as pure matter, using chemistry’s knowledge of molecules: it is H2O (two atoms of hydrogen and one of oxygen). But water is not ordinarily experienced in this term. Rather, it is most commonly experienced as a substance with properties that far exceed its internal features. This way of approaching matter converges with Bachelard’s ideas concerning the imagination of matter. In Water and Dreams: An Essay on the Imagination of Matter, Bachelard writes:

With this poetic metaphor, the author points out how our experience with water is closely related to movement:

Located in movements and organised into musical gestures and textures, intentionality in my work is revealed by structural elements such as dynamics, rhythm, kinetic energy, colour, timbre, tone and grain. Aural and visual components are composed and composited to express, reflect or suggest feelings, thoughts, expectations and reactions.

The received meaning of such work is elicited from the organisation of gestures and textures and the way the materials relate to each other. The reception also involves the experience that a viewer-listener historically entertains with the matter presented. Often, the mental imagery directly links sound and moving image to tactile impressions, conceptual thoughts and all other kinds of sensory experiences. Humans need meaning and will construct it internally from the stimuli presented, in a mind-space associated with the mental image.

Mental imaging and audiovisuality

Following Bergson (see Deleuze 1966), an image is defined by Deleuze as the set of what appears (Deleuze 1986). In its cinematic manifestation, this set is a constant flux between intersecting parts in relation to a whole (Deleuze 1986).

The mental image takes on relationships, symbolic acts, intellectual feelings and is wrought with the thought of a new and direct relationship (Deleuze 1986: 203). According to Deleuze (1986), mental images are thought-figures that emerge from a chain of relations. As aural and visual movements of matter and objects unfold, the chain of relation corresponds to what appears to us. In other terms, images act and react on other images, providing meaning that is beyond the audiovisual content itself. Action, perception and affection are built in an interconnection of relationships. It is this chain of relationships that constitute the mental image (Deleuze 1986: 204).

The useful part of Deleuze’s idea is that perception is largely based on relations between individual objects. A sound associated with an image adds its own contribution to the idea of the mental image. In this context, the relationship between seeing and hearing is central to the process of mental imaging. Further, the relationship between all of our senses is connected in our mind. The relationship between seeing, hearing and feeling is thus at the heart of the process of mental imagery.

In her article On Stan Brakhage and Visual Music (2008), Maryline Brakhage explains the concept of “physiological relationship between seeing and hearing in the making of a work of art in film” evoked by Stan Brakhage. According to the filmmaker, the organisation of colours, lines, shapes and sounds “weaves a complexity of sensory truths to which we respond with our whole nervous system and deeply known physicality of being, as the sources of that knowing interact as felt response within the intricacies of mind” (Brakhage 1982, cited in Brakhage 2008).

A mental image is associated with a mind-space where our full body is engaged.

A mental image is a mind-space where we can hear, see, feel and act out our perceptions. A mind-space is where we can construct sense.

Metaphors and symbolism

To discuss meaning, we must pay attention to the way a viewer-listener talks about her/his experience with the work. Indeed, metaphorisation and reception processes are strongly linked.

According to Delalande (1998), who has studied metaphorisation in a purely sonic context, metaphors are constructed by a listener when s/he attempts to describe sounds. These metaphors happen at two levels. First, a listener can imagine descriptive metaphors to label different types of sound (related to the morphology of the sound), such as muted blow, splashing, impact, scraping (Delalande 1998: 39). When related to actions, these sounds act on each other, and, in a symbolic way, act on the listener. For example, wind in your hair, blows to the stomach or nails on a blackboard. Secondly, metaphors can be articulated into narratives or complex images in a more personal way (Delalande 1998: 27): like swimming in the waves, like walking in the sand. The metaphors used will likely differ from one person to another. The story of this non-story is the fuzzy affect that rises in the listener’s mind and body. As is the same with videomusic.

Ultimately, videomusic provides a musical experience enacted by both visual and aural materials. A visual gesture or texture reflected in the sound, or vice versa, is a metaphor. In Vagues, the high-pitched sound of the violin has nothing to do with the water splash seen. But the energy is mutually reflected, giving a meaning that goes beyond the simple relation between the movement of the water splash and the sound presented with it. The sound becomes the metaphorical meaning of the image. This meaning may be alarm, accident, fear, etc. There are many possible interpretations.

My practice focuses on the idea that the sound/image coupling becomes a symbolic link that articulates human experience with movement and matter. This approach, rooted in an observation of the natural environment, became particularly important in the composition of Vagues.

The meta-narrative arc is partly guided by the poem The sea, by Pablo Neruda. Here is an excerpt:

Inspired by the three last lines of the excerpt, the final scene of Vagues presents a symbolic element: a foot in the water (see Figure 16.6). In literature, water symbolises life, purity, growth, birth and rebirth, among other things. This final scene may reflect one of these symbols, influencing the way meaning is constructed for the whole work. I recorded this video with the intention to capture just the water waves. My foot appeared in the shot by accident. This occurrence defined my work on meaning and led to my personal way to address it.

Figure 16.6 Still from Vagues. My foot in the water.

Figure 16.6 Still from Vagues. My foot in the water.

Note to the reader

Many of the ideas presented here are the result of conversations, lectures and exchanges with Prof. Jean Piché, who sketched them early out. The author is indebted to his foundational contributions to the field.

References

  • Bachelard, G. (1983) Water and Dreams: An Essay on the Imagination of Matter (trans. from French by E. Farrell). Dallas: Pegasus Foundation.
  • Bergala, A., et al. (1986) Le cerveau, c’est l’écran: Entretien avec Gilles Deleuze. Cahiers du Cinéma. (380). pp. 24–32.
  • Brakhage, M. (2008) On Stan Brakhage and Visual Music. Vantage Point [blog], 31 January. Available online: https://vantagepointmagazine.wordpress.com/2008/01/31/on-stan-brakhage-and-visual-music/ [Last Accessed 10/11/19].
  • Delalande, F. (1998) Music Analysis and Reception Behaviours: Sommeil by Pierre Henry. Journal of New Music Research. 27(1–2). pp. 13–66.
  • Deleuze, G. (1966) Le bergsonisme. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.
  • Deleuze, G. (1986) Cinema 1: The Movement-Image (trans. from French by H. Tomlinson; B. Habberjam). London: The Athlone Press.
  • Godoy, R.I.; Leman, M. (2010) Musical Gestures: Sound, Movement, and Meaning. New York: Routledge.
  • Gritten, A.; King, E. (eds). (2006) Music and Gesture. Burlington: Ashgate.
  • Hatten, R.S. (2006) A Theory of Musical Gesture and Its Application to Beethoven and Schubert. In: A. Gritten; E. King (eds.) Music and Gesture. Burlington: Ashgate.
  • Kastner, J. (2012) Introduction: Art in the Age of the Anthropocene. In: J. Kastner (ed.) Nature. Cambridge: The MIT Press.
  • Lee, M.C.-Y. (2016) Musical Intentionality: Between Objects and Meaning. PhD, Cornell University.
  • Lehrer, J. (2011) The Neuroscience of Music. The Wired. Available online: www.wired.com/2011/01/theneuroscience-of-music/ [Last Accessed 10/11/19].
  • Neruda, P. (2003) The Sea. In On the Blue Shore of Silence: Poems of the Sea (trans. from Spanish by A. Reid). New York, NY: HarperCollins.
  • Oliveira, J.P. (2018) Gesture Relationship between Sound and Image. L’espace du son. Bruxelles, Belgium, 26/10/18.
  • Schafer, R.M. (1977) The Tuning of the World: Toward a Theory of Soundscape Design. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.
  • Searle, J.R. (1983) Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Smalley, D. (1997) Spectromorphology: Explaining Sound-Shapes. Organised Sound. 2(2), pp. 107–126.
  • Whalen, Z. (2004). Play Along. An Approach to Videogame Music. Game Studies. 4(1), pp. 1–31.
  • Wishart, T. (1996) On Sonic Art. Amsterdam: Overseas Publishers Association.
  • Zummer, T. (2001) Projection and Dis/embodiment: Genealogies of the Virtual. In: C. Iles (ed.) Into the Light: The Projected Image in American Art, 1964–1977. New York: Whitney Museum of American Art.

Film/Media

..................Content has been hidden....................

You can't read the all page of ebook, please click here login for view all page.
Reset