11

On commensurability

Liam Magee

The freedom with the constraints of ritual logic that comes from perfect mastery of that logic is what makes it possible for the same symbol to refer back to realities that are opposed in terms of the axiomatics of the system itself. Consequently, although it is not inconceivable that a rigorous algebra of practical logics might one day be written, it will never be done unless it is understood that logical logic, which only speaks of them negatively, if at all, in the very operations through which it constitutes itself by denying them, is not equipped to describe them without destroying them. It is a question of reconstituting the ‘fuzzy’, flexible, partial logic of this partially integrated system of generative schemes which, being partially mobilized in relation to each particular situation, produces, in each case, below the level of the discourse and the logical control that it makes possible, a ‘practical’ definition of the situation and the functions of the action (which are almost always multiple and interlocking), and which, with the aid of a simple yet inexhaustible combinatory, generates the actions best suited to fulfil these functions with the limits of the available means (Bourdieu 1990).

Several of the preceding chapters compared approaches to describing or representing knowledge within particular fields. One way of characterising these studies is that they are seeking to understand what might be termed, following Kuhn (1970), the commensurability of ontologies and their associated formalisms and frameworks. The present chapter discusses the question of commensurability in more theoretical terms, stepping through several philosophical positions to arrive at the basis for the framework presented in the next chapter. So far, commensurability has been about both the explicit conceptual commitments of knowledge systems, and an implicit ‘something’ which sits behind them. But what sorts of ‘somethings’ are these; what is it that can be said to be commensurable or otherwise? Not just the systems themselves, otherwise ontology matching techniques would presumably be sufficient—there would be no need to step outside the system to glean further information. Rather, it is the constellation of beliefs, assumptions, commitments, intentions, structures and practices held by the people responsible for those systems, who design and use them. Since people also engage in a range of other social constellations and configurations, it would be accurate to speak of the dedicated cultures—organisational, communal, national or global—responsible for knowledge systems. This amorphous kind of entity will be given greater specificity in Chapter 12, ‘A framework for commensurability’; however, its description will invariably be indebted to, and share, many of the features exhibited by canonical ‘structural’ accounts of socialised knowledge: Kuhnian paradigms, Foucauldian epistemes and Quinean conceptual schemes.

The discussion of the present chapter begins, then, with a survey of these significant developments. It follows with an examination of several notable critiques of these different brands of conceptual relativism, made by Davidson and Derrida. These debates remain of central concern to contemporary theories of knowledge. Nonetheless they belong to a preceding generation of scholars; to counter with a more recent debate, the discussion embarks on an interlude examining the ‘science wars’ of the 1990s, via the series of critical analyses developed by Hacking. Returning to the formative problems of describing shared conceptual schemes, the discussion then presents recent theorisations by Habermas, Brandom and Gardenfors, in more detail than was afforded in the literature review. Together the positions outlined by these authors constitute an overarching theoretical scaffolding on which a framework can be erected, rehabilitated from the relativist critiques which beset their precursors. The resulting view of conceptual cultures, interconnected through predominantly communicative practices, is not so much ‘poststructural’—through that epithet is employed below—as a more elastic and granular form of ‘structuralism’. The critical resulting move is one from ‘conceptual relativism’—the charge laid, variously, at Kuhn, Quine and Foucault—to a form of ‘conceptual perspectivism’, where concepts oriented within a culture do frame the view out onto the objects they observe, but critically permit a revisionary ‘kick-back’, both from the objects themselves, and from the intersubjective communicative sphere of other cultures and agents who also observe and engage them.

A full critical exposition of any of these authors might constitute a substantial study in itself. The apology for the abbreviated treatment offered here is only that these positions provide useful stepping stones towards the articulation of a theoretical position, which in turn provides greater specificity and robustness for the specific methods and dimensions offered in the framework description. The alternative—to do away with the theoretical artifice altogether—would set the framework adrift, as just another concocted instrument among others. It is intended that the discussion here offers the epistemological foundations, then, that orient the subsequent technical and empirical overlay that the framework and its application in the case studies provide.

A world of ‘material intangibles’: social structures, conceptual schemes and cultural perspectives

In Chapter 7, ‘An historical introduction to formal knowledge systems’, the historical survey of knowledge systems described the movement known as logical positivism, an intellectual tradition which emphasised rigorous logical analysis and an unwavering commitment to empirical observation. This line of thought, influential in the early half of the twentieth century, came under increasing critique in the post-war period. The later Wittgenstein relinquished his early normative analysis (Wittgenstein 1921) for a descriptive exploration of language games (Wittgenstein 1967); Austin suggested new lines of inquiry for analysing utterances beyond their purely truth-functional semantic content (Austin 1975), instigating new dimensions for gauging their practical effect; and Sellars demonstrated the implied metaphysics which dwelt within the purportedly pure observational propositions of empiricism (Sellars 1997). From other angles, Marxian, Saussurean and Freudian-fuelled critiques sought to expose the deep structures that lay beneath the apparent epiphenomena of social, linguistic and psychological life.

Kuhn, Foucault and Quine represent further, mature ‘refractions’ of the harsh critical light shone on the presuppositions of the positivists. Kuhn argued that science moved not due to the irrepressible spontaneity of genius, nor the industriousness of well-managed institutions, nor, even, the inherent corrective process of Popperian falsifications endemic to scientific practice. Instead, science is a puzzle-solving exercise conducted, under normal conditions, under a ‘paradigm’—a set of core theoretical tenets which laid out the problems normal scientific practice could pursue (Kuhn 1970). Foucault in turn suggested that the human sciences operated under similar epistemic structures—‘epistemes’—which gave rise to a set of broadly contiguous discursive practices (Foucault 1970). These discursive practices participate within, and help actively constitute, political structures and techniques. In short, knowledge is power in a literal sense—it is invariably imbricated in the ‘political’. Quine, finally, put forward a variant of the ‘theoretical underdetermination’ thesis—that for any given set of observational data, more than one theory could be compatible with it, and therefore a theory would always remain critically underdetermined by its evidence. Prevailing theories instead do so because of the ease of their accommodation within an encompassing conceptual scheme. Each of these points to a structural feature in the production of knowledge: paradigms change when puzzles can no longer be solved; epistemic discursive practices operate within a mutually reinforcing synergistic dynamic with power structures; rival scientific theories win out because of their fortuitous affiliation with peripheral sets of beliefs. Narratives of either the heroic individual genius—the Darwin or Einstein of their field—or of the efficient managerial enterprise—of which IBM was an early progenitor—engaging in unencumbered hypothesis testing are exposed as mythological fictions, or, at best, as radically insufficient conditions for the production of knowledge.

These kinds of structural accounts of knowledge hold considerable appeal—they permit analysis to extend beyond the surface presentation of the practices, discourses and statements that constitute the tangible aspects of knowledge. At the same time, they are materialist rather than metaphysical, showing how epistemic conceptualisations are manifest through these very tangible elements. A paradigm is just the collection of shared theories, hypotheses, puzzles, problems, experiments and data that constitute ‘normal science’ at a point in time. An episteme is similarly only exhibited through the discursive practices which constitute it. A conceptual scheme is the shared beliefs held by a scientific or knowledge culture, manifest in both its utterances and practices. Yet these concepts are not mere relinquishable or interchangeable metaphors. They reference an importantly emergent property of knowledge, in which the whole is more than the sum of parts. Just as a portrait is more than the quantities and intensities of colour which compose it, these structures organise and formalise concepts, relations and properties into crystalline frames through which objects can be known. They constitute something like the perspective or world view through which objects can be observed, inspected, analysed, described and, ultimately, acted on. It is this material quality—that these structures allow their participating agents to reach out, through conceptual frames, to the world—that differentiates the epistemological bent of scientific and knowledgeable enterprises from other, purely metaphysical kinds of conjecture.

The next two chapters, then, introduce a vocabulary to capture the characteristics of this ‘material intangible’ thing which is both part of and more than the knowledge systems it sits behind. These first structural descriptions, invariably directed towards sweeping periods of history rather than the micro-cultures which produce particular knowledge systems, nevertheless pave the way towards the articulation of a framework for describing this elusive entity.

Kuhnian paradigms

Thomas Kuhn’s The Structure of Scientific Revolutions systematised a thesis which had previously been only put forward informally in the earlier theories of authors such as Koyre, Polanyi and Feyerband. The proposition that science proceeds not as an accumulation of facts which serve to inductively corroborate some theory, the classical notion of science, but as a series of paradigms which instead determine what sorts of facts may be produced, was succinctly and compellingly elaborated here. Since its publication, it has tremendous influence in the history of science and, arguably, even greater appeal through the ‘trickle-down’ dissemination of key terms into the broader cultural lexicon. In the practice of historical and social studies of science, rival models such as Actor-Network Theory now hold sway. Nevertheless Kuhn’s thesis is a pivotal moment in the widespread recognition that the movement of science is marked not only by quantitative epistemic growth but also, and more foundationally, through qualitative epistemic shifts. These qualitative shifts are described by two key concepts, which warrant further exploration: paradigms and incommensurability.

Paradigms are, for Kuhn, the epistemological conditions under which the normal enterprise of science operates. They are the ‘ways of knowing’ which make possible the posing and solving of puzzles: ‘The existence of this strong network of commitments—conceptual, theoretical, instrumental and methodological—is a principle source of the metaphor that relates normal science to puzzle-solving’ (Kuhn 1970, p. 42). While practitioners of science exhibit a kind of ‘know-how’ imparted by a paradigm, this does not necessarily constitute ‘knowing-that’ the paradigm exists; paradigms need not be, and only infrequently are, explicit: ‘Scientists work from models acquired through education and through subsequent exposure to the literature often without quite knowing or needing to know what characteristics have given these models the status of community paradigms’ (Kuhn 1970, p. 46). Paradigms are also the grounding conditions of the scientific practices they make possible, and cannot be made explicit as form of rules, statements or axioms: ‘Paradigms may be prior to, more binding, and more complete than any set of rules for research that could be unequivocally abstracted from them’ (Kuhn 1970, p. 46). As Kuhn notes elsewhere, paradigms have a very broad extensional definition—seeming to mean a set of both implied and explicit epistemic commitments; a meta-theoretical ground on which more granular theories and experimental practice can be constructed; a process of socialisation—what scientists do to become scientists; and an historically, spatially or epistemically bounded field, separated from others before, after or around it. In fact each of these definitional facets permit further generous extensions in the application of ‘paradigm’ (or its eventual cognate partner employed here) (Kuhn 2002).

On the one hand, following its popular usage there seems little reason to limit the use of paradigm to scientific forms of knowledge only. Other disciplinary fields—academic and industrial—seem to meet some if not all of the qualifying features of paradigms. Management practices, for instance, operate within broad cultural conceptual models, which seem to undergo more or less radical transitions when they lose their efficacy for problem solving. Moreover, often the distinction between a paradigm of rigorous science and, perhaps, a broader paradigm of the science and its applications are difficult to distinguish, particularly as science itself frequently bifurcates into sub-disciplinary and inter-disciplinary fields—ontology matching, introduced in earlier chapters, is a good example of a self-contained field that borrows approaches from beyond its computational science borders. Paradigms applied to clear historical revolutions—the Copernican turn in cosmology, Newton’s laws of physics, Maxwell’s thermodynamic equations, Darwin’s theory of evolution, to take some of Kuhn’s examples—show comparatively harsh lines of theoretical demarcation, and make a compelling narrative of different ways of seeing and knowing experienced through various paradigmatic lens. In the twilight world of less spectacular transitions—but no less revolutionary, for those who go through them—such lines are more blurry. Knowledge systems constitute ideal candidate expressions of more fine-grained paradigms, and these paradigms need considerably more elastic definition.

Similarly, for Kuhn—as for Foucault, further below—paradigms are invariably expressed in historical terms; paradigms succeed each other. Yet at a more granular level, different spheres of knowledge frequently coincide, compete, intersect and merge. Kuhn allows, for example, for a physicist and a chemist to provide different definitions of a molecule, based on the different paradigms they operate under (Kuhn 1970). However, even this example assumes too rigid a distinction around an agent’s paradigmatic engagement—as though one can be either a physicist or a chemist, but not both. Paradigms operating at a useful enough level of granularity to be applied to knowledge systems need to be the sorts of structures which agents can belong to severally, and for limited durations—enough to allow self-conscious and self-reflexive examination of the key commitments belonging to one or another co-existing paradigm. This is not an arbitrary mandate imposed here, but rather a feature of the kinds of analysis which take place in the translation of knowledge systems. System analysts, at least on an implicit, phenomenological level, frequently operate within a cognitive geometry of rotating paradigms—figuring out how to describe a concept first one way, then another; how to classify an object one way, and then another; and so on. Kuhn’s paradigms all but cover these scenarios, but need to be extended down towards the ‘micro-paradigmatic’ level to be useful here. I therefore look to carry across the insights of Kuhn’s definition of ‘paradigm’, as a general set of epistemological commitments and practices, into the theoretical dimensions of the framework, while looking to refine it into a concept more applicable to more fine-grained knowledge structures.

Kuhn also introduces the even more critical term—in the context of the present study—of ‘incommensurability’. This is used in the The Structure of Scientific Revolutions to describe how rival paradigms hold ‘incommensurable ways of seeing the world and of practicing science in it’ (Kuhn 1970, p. 4). As discussed below, incommensurability is a controversial term. Incommensurable paradigms suggest, literally, that propositions belonging to one are untranslatable into those of the other. By extension, these propositions are true or false only within the frame of reference of the current paradigm. Kuhn first depicts incommensurability in optical rather than linguistic metaphors. In a key chapter titled ‘Revolutions as changes of world view’, he works carefully to avoid the most obvious accusations of relativism:

Do we, however, really need to describe what separates Galileo from Aristotle, or Lavoisier from Priestley, as a transformation of vision? Did these really see different things when looking at the same sorts of objects?’ (Kuhn 1970, p. 120).

I am… acutely aware of the difficulties created by saying that when Aristotle and Galileo looked at swinging stones, the first saw constrained fall, the second a pendulum. The same difficulties are presented in an even more fundamental form by the opening sentences of this section: though the world does not change with a change of paradigm, the scientist afterward works in a different world (Kuhn 1970, p. 121).

Rather than being an interpreter, the scientist who embraces a new paradigm is like the man wearing inverting lenses (Kuhn 1970, p. 122).

Kuhn emphasises, over and over, how different paradigms cause scientists literally to see objects differently. The constellation of concepts which compose a given paradigm structure the observational work of science. Echoing Sellars’ critique of empiricism in particular, Kuhn writes: ‘The operations and measurements that a scientist undertakes in the laboratory are not “the given” of experience but rather “the collected with difficulty”’ (Kuhn 1970, p. 126).

Moreover empirical data is experienced against a paradigmatic backdrop which provides a pre-existing construct for how the data can be organised and interpreted:

All of this may seem more reasonable if we again remember that neither scientists nor laymen learn to see the world piecemeal or item by item. Except when all the conceptual and manipulative categories are prepared in advance… both scientists and laymen sort out whole areas together from the flux of experience (Kuhn 1970, p. 128).

As these visual cues suggest, Kuhn wants perspectives to be incommensurable to the extent that perceived objects are organised in different conceptual configurations and constellations. In a later postscript (written after, and in response to, Davidson’s critique discussed below), Kuhn asserts this incommensurability is not merely terminological, and ‘they cannot be resolved simply by stipulating the definitions of troublesome terms’ (Kuhn 1970). There is, on the one hand, no immediate language capable of neutralising these conceptual and perspectival differences: ‘The claim that two theories are incommensurable is then the claim that there is no language, neutral or otherwise, into which both theories, conceived as sets of sentences, can be translated without residue or loss’ (Kuhn 2002, p. 36).

Yet, on the other, there must be a way out of the solipsistic world of a paradigm. There is both the direct ‘stimuli’ of experience, and a broader communal culture that agents under incommensurable paradigms share. This makes possible, not a neutral language, but translation between two paradigmatically committed languages: ‘Briefly put, what the participants in a communication breakdown can do is recognize each other as members of different language communities and then become translators’ (Kuhn 1970, p. 202).

Translation is then the vehicle which begins the process of persuasion and conversion to move from one paradigm to another. However, it is frequently insufficient: ‘To translate a theory or world view into one’s own language is not to make it one’s own. For that one must go native, discover that one is thinking and working in, not simply translating out of, a language that was previously foreign’ (Kuhn 1970, p. 204, my emphasis).

Paradigms are more, then, than use of a language—they are ways of knowing, ‘thinking and working’. Until scientists are thinking and acting as though the world operates under Einstein’s theory of relativity, they are not operating within the paradigm of relativity.

It is not clear, however, that these clarifications are adequate. In spite of Kuhn’s caveats, the edges or boundaries of paradigms seem immutably hard, and nothing explains quite how, except by a process of gradual elision, an individual agent’s views shift to the point of belonging to another paradigm. Yet this introduces the pain of regress to an infinity of intermediate paradigms along the way, unacceptably diluting the concept altogether. One of the steps through this difficulty is to suggest that paradigm are structures of considerably greater elasticity than Kuhn wants to allow—that ‘scientific revolutions’ represent simply quantitatively greater shifts than other, more fine-grained changes in perspectival position. Paradigmatic incommensurability then becomes a question of degree rather than kind—a measure of ‘semantic heterogeneity’ rather than a quality of conceptual structures.

Foucauldian epistemes

Foucault’s notion of episteme is more difficult to trace and delineate than Kuhnian paradigms. As Hacking (2002) notes, Foucault rarely lays out explicit definitions of concepts, nor holds on to them for long. In one of his more programmatic declarations, The Order of Things introduces epistemes indirectly as a means for describing epistemological affinities between different strands of intellectual production. To characterise the sense of the modern episteme, Foucault describes the rise of the classificatory disciplines—biology, economics and grammar—in the late eighteenth century:

We have now advanced a long way beyond the historical event we were concerned with situating—a long way beyond the chronological edges of the rift that divides in depth the episteme of the Western world, and isolates for us the beginning of a certain modern manner of knowing empiricities. This is because the thought that is contemporaneous with us, and with which, willy-nilly, we think, is still largely dominated by the impossibility, brought to light towards the end of the eighteenth century, of basing syntheses in the space of representation, and by the correlative obligations—simultaneous but immediately divided against itself—to open up the transcendental field of subjectivity, and to constitute inversely, beyond the object, what are for us the ‘quasi-transcendentals’ of Life, Labour and Language (Foucault 1970, p. 272).

In this and other descriptions, several qualities of the episteme emerge: it is historical and, unlike a paradigm, situated across rather than within particular knowledge fields. Here, an episteme appears resolutely structural—a broad, temporal swathe of beliefs and practices which constitute both our subjectivity and our concepts. For Foucault, as for Kuhn, these structures affect both ways of seeing and speaking: ‘What came surreptitiously into being between the age of the theatre and that of the catalogue was not the desire for knowledge, but a new way of connecting things both to the eye and to discourse. A new way of making history’ (Foucault 1970, p. 143).

Later, in the more programmatic text of The Archaeology of Knowledge, Foucault explicitly defines an episteme:

The analysis of discursive formations, of positivities, and knowledge in their relations with epistemological figures and with the sciences is what has been called, to distinguish it from other possible forms of the history of the sciences, the analysis of the episteme… By episteme, we mean, in fact, the total set of relations that unite, at a given period, the discursive practices that give rise to epistemological figures, sciences, and possibly formalised systems (Foucault 2002, p. 211).

Further on, he elaborates:

The episteme is not a form of knowledge or type of rationality which, crossing the boundaries of the most varied sciences, manifests the sovereign unity of a subject, a spirit, or a period; it is the totality of relations that can be discovered, for a given period, between the sciences when one analyses them at the level of discursive regularities.

The description of the episteme presents several essential characteristics therefore: it opens up an inexhaustible field and can never be closed; its aim is not to reconstitute the system of postulates that governs all the branches of knowledge (connaissance) of a given period, but to cover an indefinite field of relations. Moreover, the episteme is not a motionless figure that appeared one day with the mission of effacing all that preceded it: it is a constantly moving set of articulations, shifts, and coincidences that are established, only to give rise to others. As a set of relations between sciences, epistemological figures, positivities, and discursive practices, the episteme makes it possible to grasp the set of constraints and limitations which, at a given moment, are imposed on discourse (Foucault 2002, p. 211).

In this later explication, the structural features of an episteme appear looser, more elastic. Moreover, an episteme is directed less towards the conceptual, and more towards the discursive properties of knowledge formation. An episteme here seems disembodied of the ‘us’ which figured heavily in the description above. Rather it operates as a sort of content-less grid, a network of rules which permits certain kinds of discourse to emerge and be treated as ‘science’ or ‘knowledge’. Naturally there remain human agents in the background, enacting discursive practices, reading, writing and interpreting. However, these are extraneous to the construction of an episteme—what matters are the discursive ‘relations’, ‘rules’ and ‘regularities’. These in turn stand in various relationships to other kinds of non-discursive practices, particularly those employed in the administration of power. For Foucault, clinics, asylums and prisons are the sites par excellence, where power-driven practices, discursive and otherwise, intersect—and where an analysis of these practices might lead to their revision or erosion. Since ‘science’, as a privileged form of epistemic practice, invests particular statements with a peculiar vindicating force for the exercise of power, making explicit the conditions that particularise and legitimate them also exposes them to critique: ‘In the enigma of scientific discourse, what the analysis of the episteme questions is not its right to be a science, but the fact that it exists’ (Foucault 2002, p. 212).

Elsewhere in interviews Foucault has also emphasised the constraining character of an episteme:

If you like, I would define the episteme retrospectively as the strategic apparatus which permits of separating out from among all the statements which are possible those that will be acceptable within, I won’t say a scientific theory, but a field of scientificity, and which it is possible to say are true or false. The episteme is the ‘apparatus’ which makes possible the separation, not of the true from the false, but of what may from what may not be characterised as scientific (Foucault 1980, p. 197).

In relation to Kuhnian paradigms, then, epistemes clearly have points of affinity and divergence. Among the more notable distinctions:

image Epistemes relate discursive practices of a science to other practices—both other discursive practices of other forms of knowledge, and other, non-discursive social practices; paradigms remain hermetically sealed structures of a singular science.

image Epistemes—at least in the more explicit articulation Foucault provides in later writings—are loose, permeable structures of discursive relations, not the shared perspectives or world views which constitute paradigms.

image Epistemes are framed as ‘rules’ and ‘regularities’ discerned by an observer—the ‘archaeologist’ of knowledge; paradigms are, while still unconscious to the practitioners of science, much closer to the surface, and at least partially describable by those practitioners.

image Epistemes function to make possible and legitimate certain kinds of statements within a broader nexus of power; paradigms function specifically for ‘normal science’ to solve puzzles—only indirectly, and coincidentally, do they engage with discourse.

There are, however, features common to paradigms and epistemes: they are largely unconscious for those who engage them, and require particular interpretive tools or methods to discover them; they are not purely conceptual constructs, but also are exhibited within social practices (discursive and otherwise); both reflect social features of a culture or community, rather than an individualistic psychological state of mind; and both involve some form of ‘orientation’ towards the objects under description—through orientation must be understood in an active sense, as actively constituting rather than merely passively observing those objects. These features carry over to the description of a more fine-grained construct in the framework ahead. Both also offer the problem of how statements can be translated across epistemic or paradigmatic boundaries—a theme returned to below.

Quinean conceptual schemes

Quine’s notion of conceptual schemes fits within the generously extended family, which also includes Kuhnian paradigms and Foucauldian epistemes. As with epistemes, it is difficult to get a definitive view as to what a conceptual scheme is. In a late interview Quine admits: ‘The only meaning I attached to it is a vague one. Namely, the conceptual scheme would be the more abstract general structure of one’s overall theory’ (Quine 1992).

Echoing a famous Quinean sentiment, that science is ‘self-conscious common sense’, conceptual schemes embrace theories of both scientific and everyday varieties (Quine 1964). While conceptual schemes might connote a sort of cognitive structure, for Quine, they are equally ‘cultural posits’. As theories, ultimately they have an explanatory function:

As an empiricist I continue to think of the conceptual scheme of science as a tool, ultimately, for predicting future experience in the light of past experience… For my part I do, qua lay physicist, believe in physical objects and not Homer’s gods; and I consider it a scientific error to believe otherwise. But in point of epistemological footing the physical objects and the gods differ only in degree and not in kind. Both sorts of entities enter our conception only as cultural posits (Quine 1980, p. 44).

Conceptual schemes of all sorts are irretrievably bound to a language, for Quine: ‘Conceptualization on any considerable scale is inseparable from language’ (Quine 1964, p. 3). He is keen to show that linguistic translation generally, and the special kind of conceptual scheme inherent in scientific theory specifically, suffer the same fate of indeterminacy. For any set of sensory stimuli, there are many more or less meritorious theories to account for them; analogously, for any source language, there are many more or less adequate translations into a target language. For Quine, the idea of a direct ‘sense-datum language’ capable of reporting just the facts is one of the two infamous ‘dogmas of empiricism’, which he attributes to the more naive leanings of positivism (the other dogma is that there can be a strict separation between analytic and synthetic statements) (Quine 1980). Empiricism instead must be rehabituated to the a priori conceptual structures capable of organising perceptions, or else suffer a form of circularity: ‘small wonder that the quest for sense data should be guided by the same sort of knowledge that prompts it’ (Quine 1964, p. 2).

Unlike the rigid characterisation of paradigms, conceptual schemes admit of ongoing partial and ‘self-conscious’ revision. Scientific discovery differs in degree rather than kind from other kinds of belief, precisely because it accepts revisionary evidence. Rather than the relativism of pluralised conceptual schemes, though, Quine thinks it is possible to be epistemically committed to a set of beliefs when none better present themselves:

Have we now so far lowered our sights as to settle for a relativistic doctrine of truth…? Not so. The saving consideration is that we continue to take seriously our own particular aggregate science, our own particular world-theory or loose total fabric of quasi-theories, whatever it may be. Unlike Descartes, we own and use our beliefs of the moment, even in the midst of philosophizing, until what is vaguely called scientific method we change them here and there for the better. Within our own total evolving doctrine, we can judge truth as earnestly and absolutely as can be; subject to correction, but that goes without saying (Quine 1964, pp. 24–25).

The problem of under-determination does not just relate to the relationship of data to theory—it equally applies to translation of one theory to another. Multiple viable translations are always possible: ‘manuals for translating one language into another can be set up in divergent ways, all compatible with the totality of speech dispositions, yet incompatible with one another’ (Quine 1980, p. 27). Here it is not that the languages or theories are untranslatable; rather, they are translatable in many different ways. And it is the translations themselves which are incommensurable—‘incompatible’, in Quine’s words—with each other. He emphasises this point with a lengthy thought experiment—what happens when a linguist is faced with some unknown language presented by an informant? The preconditions of the experiment are that there is no interpreter, and the language is not a ‘kindred’ one for the linguist (bears no common cognates or derivations). The linguist is presented with a word, ‘gavagai’, in the presence of a rabbit. The linguist then employs a steady process of elimination, with the aim of deriving the translation ‘gavagai = rabbit’. One of the eventually excluded possibilities is that of equivalence based on stimulus meaning, the sense derived from pure experience of the rabbit-phenomenon: perhaps the word ‘gavagai’ relates to this perception and not the actual animal? (Quine 1964, pp. 31–35). Another is that of occasion sentences, which refer to a particular circumstance of perceiving the rabbit—is the perceiver in a state of ‘gavagai’, then, on remarking of the rabbit? Or is the rabbit instead in a particular state indicated by ‘gavagai’, for example, that of being in position to be shot? (Quine 1964, pp. 35–41). Yet another possibility is that of observational sentences: does ‘gavagai’ relate instead to the phenomenological happening of an observation of a rabbit? (Quine 1964, pp. 41–46). Even after these possibilities are systematically eliminated under controlled circumstances, there is no guarantee of synonymity: ‘Who knows but what the objects to which this term applies are not rabbits after all, but mere stages, or brief temporal segments, of rabbits?’ (Quine 1964, p. 51). Even if the stimulus meaning—the responses of the informant hearing ‘gavagai’ on sight of the rabbit—is consistent with the linguist’s interpretation of the word ‘rabbit’, Quine argues that the extra-stimuli requirements for understanding the use of a term differ radically: ‘the whole apparatus [for using a term] are interdependent, and the very notion of term is as provincial to our culture as are those associated devices… Occasion sentences and stimulus meaning are general coin; terms and reference are local to our conceptual scheme’ (Quine 1964, p. 53). There is ultimately no recourse to sense data or an ideal language for devising a singular mapping between sentences or theory-fragments:

Sentences translatable outright, translatable by independent evidence of stimulatory occasions, are sparse and must woefully under-determine the analytical hypotheses on which the translation of all further sentences depends… There can be no doubt that rival systems of analytical hypotheses can fit the totality of speech behaviour to perfection, and can fit the totality of dispositions to speech behaviour as well, and still specify mutually incompatible translations of countless sentences insusceptible of independent control (Quine 1980, p. 72).

As noted earlier, conceptual schemes seem broadly contiguous with other structural notions of paradigms and epistemes. Quine’s critique of positivism is derived from a logical rather than historical analysis, and consequently specific kinds of historical and cultural ‘posits’ are argued for analytically rather than demonstrated through cases. Consequently their definition is considerably abstract; nevertheless some concrete characteristics can be identified:

image Conceptual schemes are in the first instance cultural rather than cognitive entities.

image Conceptual schemes are elastic, and capable of endless revision.

image More than one conceptual scheme can arise to account for the phenomena being described.

image There can also be more than one translation between two conceptual schemes.

There are several implications of Quine’s analysis for the treatment of knowledge systems: first, it admits the possibility both of multiple, equally valid knowledge systems in a given domain, and also, of multiple ways of aligning or matching these systems. Second, such systems do not describe the ‘sense data’, or objects belonging to a domain, neutrally, but bring to bear the background cultural ‘posits’ inherited by their authors. Third, these ‘posits’ invariably undergo revision—hence schemes should not be seen in rigid terms like the systems themselves, but as flexible networks which ‘cohere’ into reified form in systems. Hence uncovering background concepts is necessarily a more heuristic and interpretive exercise.

These three accounts—Kuhnian paradigms, Foucauldian epistemes and Quinean conceptual schemes—are now ‘classic’ structural treatments of knowledge systems in the broad sense, and deserve detailed coverage. The theoretical underpinnings of the ontology commensurability framework build on these treatments, but rely on more recent work of Habermas, Brandom and Gardenfors, which adds both greater descriptive precision about what schemes are, and causal suggestiveness for how it is that multiple schemes arise. In the meantime, the specifically structural character of conceptual schemes and its analogues was to receive significant critical attention in the 1970s; two of these critical lines are reviewed in the next section.

De-structuring critiques: struggling with systems, structures and schemes

What has been described as the ‘structural’ tendencies in Kuhn, Foucault and Quine is more by way of general shared analogical traits than any strong identifying ideological tenets. Only Foucault could be tentatively affiliated with the intellectual movement known as ‘structuralism’—and was, in any case, progressively characterised as a post-structuralist in his later work. Nevertheless, as the discussion above shows, there are common threads between these authors, and indeed others of the same period. These in turn were to come under critical fire from various directions. The critiques by Davidson and Derrida are notable both from the prominence of their respective authors, and for the ‘anti-schematic’ and ‘post-structural’ movements to which they gave rise in various strains of linguistics, cultural studies and philosophy of language. The general outline of these critiques is traced in the next two sections.

‘On the very idea’…

Davidson explicitly responds to the positions espoused by Kuhn and Quine, suggesting they represent various forms of conceptual relativism. Bracketing Whorfian languages and Kuhnian paradigms under the general heading of Quinean ‘conceptual schemes’, Davidson offers a basic outline of the conceptual relativist’s position:

Conceptual schemes, we are told, are ways of organizing experience; they are systems of categories that give form to the data of sensation; they are points of view from which individuals, cultures, or periods survey the passing scene. There may be no translating from one scheme to another, in which case the beliefs, desires, hopes, and bits of knowledge that characterize one person have no true counterparts for the subscriber to another scheme. Reality itself is relative to a scheme: what counts as real in one system may not in another (Davidson 2006, p. 186).

The inherent paradox involved in such as position is that explaining how conceptual schemes differ presupposes an underlying common language—and corresponding conceptual scheme. The act of description shows how the terms of both schemes can be mapped onto a higher level set of terms, the language of the description itself: ‘Different points of view make sense, but only if there is a common co-ordinate system on which to plot them; yet the existence of a common system belies the claim of dramatic incomparability’ (Davidson 2006, p. 197).

Davidson distinguishes between two ‘failures of translatability’—complete and partial (Davidson 2006, p. 198). Complete untranslatability means no substantial translation between two languages; partial means some sentences can be translated, some cannot. In going after complete untranslatability, Davidson further distinguishes between the following two scenarios: the first, where speakers talk about different worlds using the same language; the second, where speakers talk about the same world using different languages. The first case makes the mistake of exercising one of Quine’s dogmas of empiricism, relying on the distinction between analytic and synthetic truths. The second case, Davidson argues, commits an analogous though different sin of relying on a distinction between ‘scheme’ and ‘content’. This so-called ‘third dogma’—extending the two Quinean dogmas discussed above—is one which Quine himself is guilty of, as are Kuhn and other purveyors of conceptual relativism.

Davidson proceeds to argue that this dogma assumes conceptual schemes are seen as either ‘organising’ or ‘fitting in’ with some ‘content’—in turn, such content is either ‘reality’ or ‘experience’. Taken actively, schemes must organise pluralities of worldly or experiential content. But such pluralities must, for Davidson, consist of observable ‘individualities’, which in the final resort can be shown and demonstrated to other linguistic speakers, even when languages differ. In such cases, ‘a language that organizes such entities must be a language very like our own’ (Davidson 2006, p. 203). Taken passively, schemes must generate true statements of the content they purport to represent: ‘the point is that for a theory to fit or face up to the totality of possible sensory evidence is for that theory to be true’ (Davidson 2006, p. 204). For the thesis of complete untranslatability, it must be possible for two schemes both to be ‘largely true but untranslatable’ (Davidson 2006, p. 205). Davidson then invokes Tarski’s Convention T to demonstrate that on ‘our best intuition as to how the concept of truth is used’, translation is in fact an ‘essential notion’:

according to Tarski’s Convention T, a satisfactory theory of truth for a language L must entail, for every sentence s of L, a theorem of the form ‘s is true if and only if p’ where ‘s’ is replaced by a description of s and ‘p’ by s itself if L is English, and by a translation of s into English if L is not English (Davidson 2006, p. 205).

Understanding that a sentence is true in another language involves being able to translate that sentence, or a description of it, into a native language. Consequently, a theory of schemes which are mutually and completely untranslatable (or incommensurable), yet which together contain large sets of true sentences, must lapse into incoherence.

The case for partial untranslatability (or incommensurability) rests on this first result. Davidson invokes what he terms a ‘principle of charity’—we understand speakers of other languages (and scientific theories or conceptual schemes) by ‘knowing or assuming a great deal about the speaker’s beliefs’ (Davidson 2006, p. 207). Accordingly, ‘we make maximum sense of the words and thoughts of others when we interpret in a way which optimizes agreement (this includes room, as we said, for explicable error, i.e. differences of opinion)’ (Davidson 2006, p. 207). On this view, substantial agreement needs to precede even the possibility of disagreement; rival conceptual schemes are deflated for local ‘differences of opinion’. Less otiose, for Davidson partial untranslatability is nonetheless equally incoherent, and as a final consequence, the third dogma of empiricism—that of scheme and reality—can at this point be happily dispensed with: ‘In giving up the dualism of scheme and world, we do not give up the world, but reestablish unmediated touch with the familiar objects whose antics make our sentences and opinions true or false’ (Davidson 2006, p. 208).

The incommensurability of madness

Derrida’s early critique of Foucault, written in 1963, is lengthy and complex, pivoting in part on a close reading and interpretation of Descartes, and of Foucault’s reading of Descartes (Derrida 2001). In broad terms it mirrors the broad structure of the critique Davidson levies at Kuhn and Quine; it is also worth noting that this critique is directed towards an early variant of Foucault’s ‘structuralist’ thought, which is revised heavily by the time of the works cited above. Rather than follow the argument in depth, I extract some salient lines of critique to demonstrate the analogy with Davidson; points which also go to the heart of the structuralist program.

In Madness and Civilization, Foucault attempted to mark an epistemic break in the eighteenth century in the dialogue between Reason and Madness (Foucault 1965). During the Middle Ages and the Renaissance, Foucault argues, Madness could be publicly paraded—literally and discursively—as evidenced in the texts of Rabelais, Shakespeare and Cervantes. The Enlightenment marks the breakdown of this dialogue into two separate monologues; or rather, as madness became increasingly silenced through the general institutionalisation of rationality and the specific institutions of psychiatry, into the monologue of Reason and the silence of Madness. Foucault’s project is to provide a history of that silence, to be the voice through which, retrospectively and belatedly, Madness can once again speak. Transposed to more convenient vocabulary, Reason and Madness are historically incommensurable, riven apart by the rationalist episteme since the Enlightenment.

Derrida’s overt object of criticism is whether this project is possible and coherent—or whether, rather, in attempting to liberate Madness from its Enlightenment constraints, Foucault merely repeats the constraining gestures of Reason: ‘Would not the archaeology of silence by the most efficacious and subtle restoration, the repetition, in the most irreducibly ambiguous meaning of the word, of the act perpetrated against madness—and be so at the very moment when this act is denounced?’ (Derrida 2001, p. 41).

And later: ‘Thus, not an expediency, but a different and more ambitious design, one that should lead to a praise of reason… but this time of a reason more profound than that which opposes and determines itself in a historically determined conflict [with madness]’ (Derrida 2001, p. 51).

More obliquely, Derrida also critiques the historical structures Foucault erects to describe the broad epistemic transitions from a dialogical—if strained—relationship between Reason and Madness towards an exclusionary one marked by the advent of the Enlightenment. At one point Derrida directs attention to the apparent arbitrariness with which Foucault cites Descartes as an exemplar of a new, emerging and ominously silencing attitude towards Madness, precisely as Reason is receiving its definitive articulation: ‘It is an example as sample, and not as model’ (Derrida 2001, p. 51). What epistemic status, then, does this ‘sample’ have in a history of madness? Its representativeness of Enlightenment constructions of madness, at least, is for Derrida highly questionable.

Later, describing Foucault’s project, Derrida writes: ‘But I wonder whether, when one is concerned with history (and Foucault wants to write a history), a strict structuralism is possible, and, especially, whether, if only for the sake of order and within the order of its own descriptions, such a study can avoid all etiological questions’ (Derrida 2001, p. 52).

Derrida wants to ask what relationship a singular passage from Descartes—later to be analysed in considerable depth—has to the broad historical structure Foucault seeks to account for: ‘Is this “act of force” described in the dimension of theoretical knowledge and metaphysics [that of Descartes’ Meditations], a symptom, a cause, a language?’ (Derrida 2001, p. 53). If an example does not function as either cause or effect, but simply counts as a kind of suggestive evidence of the existence of a structure, what motivates its selection—and not others, in particular potential counter-examples? Although at some remove from Davidson’s line of argument, there is a common concern with the relationship of the ‘totality’ of the structure to its parts—’individualities’ for Davidson, the unspecified ‘exemplarity’ of Descartes for Derrida. A lack of methodological specificity regarding the role of exemplary parts is met by an equivalent concern voiced earlier: that different historical periods have complex, shifting and overlapping trajectories regarding the conceptual delineations they make. Consequently it is difficult to voice the history of a notion—’Madness’—which itself has undergone considerable transformation over time: ‘Foucault, in rejecting the psychiatric or philosophical material that has always emprisoned the mad, winds up employing—inevitably—a popular and equivocal notion of madness, taken from an unverifiable source’ (Derrida 2001, p. 49).

Just as, for Davidson, the attempt to separate content and scheme collapses—and along with it, the problem of schematic incommensurability—so, for Derrida, the various cases of conceptual and historical structures—between, respectively, the concepts of Madness and History, and medieval and classical periods of treatment of madness—are compromised. On the one hand the conceptual, structural opposition between Reason and Madness is shown to be more complicated—that trying to speak the history of a singularised entity called ‘Madness’ risks objectifying it as an object of an historicising and alienating Reason all over again. On the other hand, the historical ‘structures’ in which these concepts figure are shown to be less stable, and less demonstrable by way of exemplary cases, than Foucault’s clear delineations might suggest.

Resurrecting structures

Davidson and Derrida’s critiques are of the more strenuous variety directed towards the implied relativist tendencies in any talk of conceptual structure, in either abstract or concrete historical terms. It seems anachronistic, then, to commit to untranslatable ‘ontological’ entities such as paradigms, epistemes and schemes. Yet, as discussed below, geometric metaphorisations of cultural and cognitive structure continue to emerge in more recent theories. One way of avoiding the types of traps Davidson and Derrida might lay out for prospective structuralist tendencies of this sort would be to suggest such theories adopt the kinds of tempering characteristics at least implied in Foucault and Quine—to suggest that conceptual schemes are elastic, supple sorts of historical and cultural objects, without clear and rigid boundaries or demarcations. As if to help avoid this impasse, at one stage Davidson makes a crucial elision—caricaturing the relativist’s position, he notes: ‘the test of [schematic] difference remains failure or difficulty of translation’ (Davidson 2006, p. 202, my emphasis). While Kuhn stresses complete untranslatability, Quine in particular wants to acknowledge that translation is a rough-and-ready, more or less inexact and partial process, where ‘difficulty’ need not necessarily elide into ‘failure’. This arguably accords well with everyday intuitions about translation, even between the ‘micro-languages’ of various organisational and cultural settings, as well as, more concretely, between the various orientations adopted within knowledge systems. And it ought to be possible to continue to think ‘schematically’—that is, retaining the language of conceptual schemes and structures—just so long as those schemes are treated in a suitable elastic sense. The question of commensurability can then be posed in many-valued degrees rather than two-valued kind—as a question of ‘how’ rather than ‘whether’ two schemes are commensurable. Moreover, schemes can be happily readopted having been denuded of any palpable and reified ontological form—and instead be treated as convenient bundles of particular concepts, beliefs, statements and practices of some more or less aligned group of actors. Schemes and structures, in a rehabilitated and analytical rather than ontological form, can serve a practical purpose in describing both the tacit and explicit statements of systems, and the notion of commensurability can further serve a derivatively useful function as a measure of the ‘difficulty’ translating one set of schematic commitments into another.

Interlude: constructions of science

In The Social Construction of What? Hacking provides a contemporary review on the kinds of positions reflected in the discussions above (Hacking 1999). He reviews not only the by now ‘classic’ articulations of what has become known as ‘social constructionism’—through the work of Kuhn, Foucault and others—but also a series of more recent exchanges which took place over the course of the 1990s, in the course of the so-called ‘Science Wars’. The Sokal hoax, in which a fictitious article, hyperbolically overblown with postmodern cliches, was published in a literary theory journal, supplied the catalytic impetus for the debate which followed. Hacking, in his account, is less interested in accounting for the specifics of the exchange than in endeavouring to reconfigure the crudely bifurcated divide of ‘realist’ and ‘constructionist’ camps into a more finely discriminated constellation of positions.

The purpose of covering Hacking’s analysis here is to demonstrate the ongoing resonance of the theoretical issues canvassed so far, and to suggest some ways that the proposed framework can sidestep at least the more naive excesses of relativism, if not several other related species of nominalism and constructivism. One of the risks of applying the sorts of terms adopted in this study is that it itself can be relativised to a particular cultural conceptual scheme—one which effectively mitigates its putative claims towards truth or, less ambitiously, towards usefulness. By sifting through the distinctions Hacking raises, the argument can escape with a lesser charge of ‘conceptual perspectivism’, a viewpoint which holds that correspondence theories of truth are usefully augmented, rather than replaced by, coherentist and consensual notions. As a consequence the theoretical underpinnings of the study would then be exonerated of the more exacting crimes of relativism and incoherence to which Davidson and others have charged some of the foundational structuralist claims laid out above.

Hacking begins by connecting the brand of conceptual relativism and social constructionism held by Kuhn, Foucault and others to an older philosophical position of nominalism:

Constructionists tend to maintain that classifications are not determined by how the world is, but are convenient ways in which to represent it. They maintain that the world does not come quietly wrapped up in facts. Facts are the consequences of ways in which we represent the world. The constructionist vision here is splendidly old-fashioned. It is a species of nominalism. It is countered by a strong sense that the world has an inherent structure that we discover (Hacking 1999, p. 33).

Hacking wants to show that exploded out of epithetic form, ‘realist’ and ‘constructivist’ positions need not entail mutually exclusive propositions. He argues that while the natural sciences can be considered as describing reality compellingly, in ways which mesh with our practical efforts to orient ourselves to the world, a degree of social construction is frequently entailed as well. Aspects of the opposition degenerate into a ‘two sides of the same coin’ type of argument: for Hacking, rather, a scientific theory can be both the best account of naturalistic phenomena we have—it can even be ‘real’, ‘as real as anything we know’ (Hacking 1999)—and yet equally belong to a given historical episteme or paradigm, exist in a given conceptual scheme, and be socially constructed as much as any cultural or social—that is, as any identifiably unnatural—thing might be. This account explicates what is implicit in the theoretical overlays of Kuhn and Foucault in particular, and suggests they hold a more complicated relationship between ‘scheme’ and ‘reality’ than the charge of naive, fullblown relativism often laid against them would indicate.

Elsewhere Rorty characterises this sentiment in perspicuous fashion:

‘Relativism’ is the view that every belief on a certain topic, or perhaps about any topic, is as good as every other. No-one holds this view. Except for the occasional cooperative freshman, one cannot find anybody who says that two incompatible opinions on an important topic are equally good. The philosophers who get called ‘relativists’ are those who say that the grounds for choosing between such opinions are less algorithmic than had been thought’ (Rorty 1982, p. 166).

Rorty is here keen to separate pragmatism from the stigmatism of relativism and irrationalism. Hacking is broadly sympathetic with the kind of pragmatism Rorty advances; however he wants also to pursue a demarcation of these positions in more fine-grained terms. In circumscribing the field of positions identifiably constructionist, Hacking sets up a simple analytic schema of three independent variables: a theory is constructionist if it rates highly on scales of contingency, nominalism and external explanations of stability. For the adamant constructionist, scientific ‘truths’ are quintessentially contingent ones:

The constructionist maintains a contingency thesis. In the case of physics, (a) physics (theoretical, experimental, material) could have developed in, for example, a nonquarky way, and, by the detailed standards that would have evolved with this alternative physics, could have been as successful as recent physics has been by its detailed standards (Hacking 1999, pp. 78–79).

The opposite side of this coin is inevitability—the idea of regardless who invented, discovered, studied or funded what, ‘if successful physics took place, then it would inevitably have happened in something like our way’ (Hacking 1999, p. 79). The inevitabilist position would claim that even some alien species, following a separate historical, linguistic and cultural path, and having embarked on a project to discover physical laws, must necessarily have derived something like our physics; if this is the case, no amount of cultural deviation and contingency as to the superficiality of discovery change the substantive content of the discovery. Hacking cites ‘Maxwell’s Equations, the Second Law of Thermodynamics, the velocity of light’ (Hacking 1999, p. 79) as particularly unshakeable discoveries. He then suggests that the position of the inevitabilists, unlike those of the discoveries themselves, is ‘not derived by inference from experience’ but rather is prompted by ‘a sensibility that arises in a great many people in Western civilization who are attracted to scientific styles of reasoning’ (Hacking 1999, p. 79). As this quote suggests, Hacking’s analysis contains a sense that at heart both contingency and inevitability theses arise from a culturally instilled aesthetic sensibility, rather than from rational calculation. On the inevitabilist side, incompatible views are always trivially so—capable of reconciliation once the superficial contingencies of disparate lexical and observational items have been worked through by holders of those views. A believer in epistemic contingency permits of radically different conceptual organisations, though how this might be so would be difficult to determine in advance: ‘Moreover—and this is something badly in need of clarification—the “different” physics would not have been equivalent to present physics. Not logically incompatible with, just different’ (Hacking 1999, p. 72).

Nominalism, the second variable Hacking introduces, is also is best understood against its more familiar opposite, which supposes that reality has an inherent structure waiting to be discovered:

Even if we have not got things right, it is at least possible that the world is so structured. The whole point of inquiry is to find out about the world. The facts are there, arranged as they are, no matter how we describe them. To think otherwise is not to respect the universe but to suffer from hubris… (Hacking 1999, p. 83).

Nominalism makes the opposite claim: ‘the world is so autonomous, so much to itself, that it does not even have what we call structure in itself’ (Hacking 1999, p. 72). Hacking argues that nominalists share Kant’s distinction between phenomena and noumena—the world in itself is unknowable: ‘We make our puny representations of this world, but all the structure of which we can conceive lies within our representations’ (Hacking 1999, p. 72). Words pick out groups of objects based on what appear to be their common properties. Science, as Quine would put it, ‘is self-conscious common sense’ (Quine 1980, p. 3)—in light of an evergrowing body of empirical evidence, new words are coined both to identify and differentiate that evidence. Concepts thus coined are related into structures which appear to lay bare the hidden organisations of things—but for a nominalist, these structures are not lasting reflections of the nature they mirror, they are pragmatic tools to convey a particular understanding, to achieve a given outcome. The indeterminacy of those structures—that they could be otherwise—does not necessitate perpetual and crippling doubt on behalf of the nominalist, however, unlike the caricature which would claim ‘no one is a social constructionist at 30,000 feet’ (Hacking 1999, p. 67); both Hacking and Pinker (Pinker 1995) quote Richard Dawkins as the original source of this anti-relativist quote. There is no inconsistency in holding that a given arrangement of concepts allows for considerable practical feats of engineering, for example, while questioning whether that arrangement is the only one given to adequate concordance with nature.

The final variable Hacking introduces concerns explanations of scientific stability. The constructionist position here is that science is alternatively stable or volatile at times depending at least in part on the social context in which they operate. For Hacking, the highly fluctuating states of the natural sciences in the early and middle parts of the twentieth century account for a view of science as volatile and erratic—Kuhn, Feyerabend, Popper and others were responding to unusual periods of scientific and political activity and turmoil, and consequently found discontinuities, anarchism and dialectic everywhere in what had previously been presupposed as a stable and cumulative exercise. The challenge now for sociologists and historians of science, states Hacking, is ‘to understand stability’ (Hacking 1999, p. 85), given recent decades have tended to reaffirm the glacial rather the volcanic terrain of scientific knowledge. This stability also plays into the hands of those who would like to affirm the ‘objective nature of scientific knowledge [which] has been denied by Ross… Latour… Rorty and… Kuhn, but is taken for granted by most natural scientists’ (Hacking 1999, p. 88, quoting Stephen Weinberg). Here ‘stabilists’ tend to corroborate a traditional view of science as progressionist, accumulative and rational; ‘revolutionaries’ of science affirm its epistemic and paradigmatic disruptions, generated not by internal discovery but by irrational external factors. Hacking connects these two trends with another classical distinction between rationalism and empiricism: ‘Leibniz thinks that the reasons underlying truths are internal to those truths, while Locke holds that (our confidence in) truths about the world is always external, never grounded in more than our experience’ (Hacking 1999, p. 91).

Hacking conveys a sense that, as with the previous ‘variables’, the choice here is one of temperament: ‘rationalists, at least retrospectively, can always adduce reasons that satisfy them. Constructivists, with equal ingenuity, can always find to their own satisfaction an openness where the upshot of research is settled by something other than reason’ (Hacking 1999, pp. 91–92). However, there is more at stake than a simple acknowledgement of the significance of aesthetics in determining positions on the variable scales Hacking identifies. The provocations of constructivism have an important deflationary role in the institutionalising and authoritarian tendencies of modern science. In other words, Hacking recognises the structural side-effects of Kuhn and Feyerabend’s critiques (Hacking 1999)—and elsewhere, those of Foucault also (Hacking 2002)—which cause science to rethink its ontological foundations and perhaps accept, in Hacking’s terms, a ‘kind of objectivity… that strives for a multitude of standpoints’ (Hacking 1999, p. 96).

What can be taken from this analysis for considering the commensurability of knowledge systems? It has already been emphasised that a simple binary opposition of commensurable-incommensurable is inadequate, and this assessment need to be treated more as scaled, multidimensional constructs. Hacking’s three variables for describing a more general orientation towards science—contingency, nominalism and stability—also suggest a similarly scalar rather than binary application. Moreover, the variables themselves are useful in rating the standpoints of more fine-grained entities like knowledge systems; accordingly they will be carried over, in less abstract form, to the presentation of system dimensions in the next chapter. More generally, Hacking’s analysis goes after what he terms elsewhere ‘historical ontologies’ (Hacking 2002)—positions which, though framed in contemporary dialogue, in fact exhibit historical resonances with earlier articulations, similarly locked into intractable dialogical structures with their contraries. Tracing such ‘irresoluble differences’, all the better to ‘emphasize philosophical barriers, real issues on which clear and honorable thinkers may eternally disagree’ (Hacking 1999, p. 68), is not, for Hacking, an exercise in intellectual vanity, but serves to exorcise both the implacable grandstanding and ‘false positive’ of facile reconciliations of various standpoints. There is an intrinsic sympathy, then, between his analysis here and the downstream exercise of assessing inter-system commensurability, by allowing differences to be exhumed in their various cultural refractions, and not to be merely reconciled algorithmically. The correcting factor in the case of system translation is that such differences are not presumed to be ‘irresoluble’ in anything like an ontological sense—this judgement, too, is one contingent on the conditions of particular situational contexts in which translation takes place.

Finally, Hacking has suggested some ways out of the impasse brought about by Davidson and Derrida, by replacing conceptual ‘relativism’ with a weaker variant of ‘perspectivism’—an acknowledgement that potentially irreconcilable views are organised within a historical structure of interdependent standpoints, which can in turn be analysed and made explicit against adroitly selected dimensional criteria. This insight can be applied no less to fine-grained ‘systems of knowledge’, in the specific technical sense referred to here, as to scientific theories and indeed the whole of science itself. The next section develops this guiding insight through the theories of Habermas, Brandom and Gardenfors, who collectively provide a rehabilitated, elasticised structural account—covering social, linguistic and cognitive aspects—of conceptual schemes, which in turn paves the way for the elaboration of the framework in the next chapter.

Elastic structures: linking the linguistic, the cognitive and the social

Habermas outlines a complex diagnostic theory of modern society which locates social pathologies in the rise of instrumental reason since the Enlightenment, and its subsequent domination over ethical and aesthetic value spheres (Habermas 1987). Within the historical emergence of secularism and capitalism, this has led to the proliferation of social systems with competing ends. In the context of my argument, this proliferation spreads down to the conceptual schemes embedded within the information systems which aid in the procedural means needed to meet such ends, and is thus a major causative factor for creating conditions of incommensurability. Brandom offers an exacting analysis of language, which builds on the insights of analytic and pragmatist twentieth-century philosophy. He outlines a fine-grained theory of meaning which emphasises the normative, pragmatist, inferentialist and holist character of language (Brandom 1994). For Brandom, this account runs against the general grain of twentieth-century semantics, which he instead suggests offers a psychological, idealist, representational and atomistic theory of meaning. Gardenfors’ work on conceptual spaces, which uses geometric metaphors to describe cognitive structures, at first glance seems incongruous against Brandom’s predominantly socialised account of meaning (Gardenfors 2000). Gardenfors, however, carefully reconciles concept use in individuals with a pragmatist standpoint which leads back out to the social.

These accounts are correctively adjusted to the kinds of critiques laid at the ‘classical’ structures described above. Gardenfors’ cognitive spaces are pliable and adaptable organisations of concepts, not, in this respect at least, dissimilar from Quine’s conceptual schemes; Brandom’s assertional structures are not the unmediated neutral language of description favoured by positivism, but sorts of trading tokens in a social ‘game of asking for and giving reasons’. Habermas’ social structures are unfortunate side-effects of an overly systematised modernity, but equally capable of interrogation and revision. These traits were certainly observable in generous readings of Kuhn, Foucault and Quine—though, as Davidson and Derrida’s readings demonstrate, it is also possible to view paradigms, epistemes and schemes as overly reified, dogmatised and fossilised structures, which suffer incoherence under scrutiny. The second ‘triumvirate’ of theoretical positions, moreover, provides a suitable overlay of cognitive, linguistic and social structures through which conceptualisations can be viewed and described. For the purpose of establishing a theoretical basis for the framework which follows, then, Gardenfors provides a thorough-going and empirical theory of conceptual schemes which serves to ground the analysis presented here; Brandom develops the broad over-arching justification for connecting such schemes to the social context in which they emerge; while Habermas offers a partially causal explanation for the structural forms of these contexts, giving at least a generalised set of reasons for why rival, incommensurable conceptual schemes should arise at all in the modern era.

Spatialising concepts

In Conceptual Spaces, Gardenfors (2000) develops a theory of conceptual representation in the cognitive science tradition developed by Rosch, Lakoff and others (Lakoff and Johnson 1980; Medin 1989; Rosch 1975), surveyed earlier in Chapter 3, ‘The meaning of meaning’. Gardenfors develops a ‘conceptual framework’, a constellation of concepts in which ‘concept’ itself figures prominently. In the first part of the book, Gardenfors presents a framework comprising:

image Conceptual spaces—A high level collection of concepts and relations, used for organising and comparing sensory, memory or imaginative experiences.

image Domains—A clustering of related concepts. Gardenfors (2000) suggests ‘spatial’, ‘colors’, ‘kinship’ and ‘sounds’ are possible concept domains.

image Quality dimensions—Generalised distinctions which determine the kinds of domains concepts belong to, such as ‘temperature’, ‘weight’, ‘height’, ‘width’ and ‘depth’. Gardenfors states: ‘The primary function of the quality dimensions is to represent various “qualities” of objects’, and, more specifically, that they can be ‘used to assign properties to objects and to specify relations among them’ (Gardenfors 2000, p. 6). Dimensions can be either phenomenal (relating to direct experience) or scientific (relating to theorisations of experience); innate or culturally acquired; sensory or abstract.

image Representations—Gardenfors discriminates between three layers of representation: the symbolic (or linguistic), the sub-conceptual (or connectionist) and the conceptual, which Gardenfors claims mediates between the other two layers. Each layer—from sub-conceptual through to symbolic—exhibits increasing degrees of granularity and abstraction of representation. Gardenfors also notes that the conceptual mediates between the parallel processing of sub-conceptual neural networks and serial processing involved in the production and interpretation of symbolic language.

image Properties—’These are means ‘for “reifying” the invariances in our perceptions that correspond to assigning properties to the perceived objects’ (Gardenfors 2000, p. 59). They are specialised kinds of concepts which occupy a ‘region’ within a single domain, delineated within the broader conceptual space by quality dimensions. A feature of properties defined in this way is that they accord both with strict and vague or fuzzy borders between properties—objects can be permitted ‘degree[s] of membership’, depending on their proximity to the centre of the property region. Both classical and prototypical theories of classification can be accommodated.

image Concepts—General (non-propertied) concepts differ from properties in that they can belong to multiple domains, and different conceptual features can gain greater salience in different contexts. Concepts are in a constant process of being added, edited and deleted within new domain arrangements; consequently, concept meaning is transient. Conceptual similarity comes on the basis of shared or overlapping domains.

The resulting framework is pragmatic and ‘instrumentalist’; the ‘ontological status’ of conceptual spaces is less relevant than that ‘we can do things with them’ (Gardenfors 2000, p. 31). Specifically, the framework ought to have ‘testable empirical consequences’ and, further, to provide a useful knowledge representation model for ‘constructing artificial systems’ (Gardenfors 2000, p. 31). One advantage of the use of geometric metaphors to describe conceptual arrangements is that it is possible to calculate approximate quantifications of semantic distance between individual concepts and concept clusters. However, the mathematisation of conceptual structures is to be taken as a heuristic rather than deterministic model—for Gardenfors, ‘we constantly learn new concepts and adjust old ones in the light of new experiences’ (Gardenfors 2000, p. 102). In light of this ever-changing configuration of concepts, any calculation of semantic proximity or distance is likely to be at best accurate at a point in time, although statistically—across time and users of conceptual clusters and relations—there may well be computable aggregate tendencies.

The arrangement of concepts and properties within conceptual spaces and domains depends on a coordinating principle of similarity:

First, a property is something that objects can have in common. If two objects both have a particular property, they are similar in some respect… Second, for many properties, there are empirical tests to decide whether it is present in an object or not. In particular, we can often perceive that an object has a specific property or not (Gardenfors 2000, pp. 60–61).

Dimensions form the basis against which similarity is assessed—a single dimension for properties, multiple dimensions for concepts. Conceptual similarity for Gardenfors is intrinsically a cognitive and theoretical notion, however, which can consequently be varied as different dimensional properties are found to be more or less salient:

For example, folk botany may classify plants according to the color or shape of the flowers and leaves, but after Linnaeus the number of pistils and stamens became the most important dimensions for botanical categorizations. And these dimensions are perceptually much less salient than the color or shape domains. Shifts of attention to other domains thus also involve a shift in overall similarity judgments (Gardenfors 2000, p. 108).

In the latter part of the book, Gardenfors then shows how his framework can be applied to traditional problems of semantics, induction and computational knowledge representation and reasoning (Gardenfors 2000). In particular he emphasises the relationship of conceptual structures to broader spheres of human action and practice. In what is an avowedly ‘pragmatist account’, meaning is put to the service of use within these spheres—though it is not equivalent to it. Unlike conventional semantics, the kind of ‘conceptual semantics’ Gardenfors espouses works down from social practice to fine-grained linguistics utterances: ‘actions are seen as the most basic entities; pragmatics consists of the rules for linguistic actions; semantics is conventionalized pragmatics… and finally syntax adds markers to help disambiguate when the context does not suffice’ (Gardenfors 2000, p. 185).

The pragmatist elements of this account fits well with the analysis of language Brandom undertakes, while the social orientation begins to bring concepts out of mind and language and into the intersubjective domain theorised by Habermas—points of accord succinctly encapsulated in the following quote: ‘In brief, I claim that there is no linguistic meaning that cannot be described by cognitive structures together with sociolinguistic power structures’ (Gardenfors 2000, p. 201). Applied to knowledge systems, Gardenfors supplies a convenient ‘first tier’ description of the kind of entity which includes the explicit conceptualisation of the system itself, and the tacit commitments which stand behind it. ‘Conceptual spaces’, standing here for Quine’s ‘conceptual schemes’, are mentalist metaphors for describing at least part of what it is that a knowledge system represents. The remaining sections add further descriptive tiers on which the framework of the study can be mounted.

Practicing with concepts

Brandom develops a contemporary account of linguistic practices grounded in the pragmatist tradition of Sellars and Rorty. Unlike Rorty, for whom all kinds of linguistic utterance were of equivalent functional significance, Brandom privileges propositional assertions as ‘fundamental speech acts’, without which other speech acts—commands, interrogatives, exclamations—would not be thinkable (Brandom 2000a). Assertions are, for Brandom, tokens in a ‘game of giving and asking for reasons’, nodal components in a vast articulated web of inferences which constitute discursive practice. The primary role of assertions is not, as a correspondence theory of truth would have it, to represent an actual state of affairs, but rather to express, or, in Brandom’s more canonical expression, to make ‘explicit what is implicit’. In a pivotal passage, he continues: ‘This can be understood in a pragmatist sense of turning something we can initially only do into something we can say: codifying some sort of knowing how in the form of a knowing that’ (Brandom 2000a, p. 8).

Where Gardenfors’ primary linguistic unit of analysis is the word, for Brandom it is the sentential structure that provides the key to ‘knowing that’, to assertion making. An atomistic orientation towards concept-use might make it appear that concepts are accumulated, one after another. For Brandom, contra Davidson, the scheme necessarily precedes the individuated concept:

One immediate consequence of such an inferential demarcation of the conceptual is that one must have many concepts in order to have any. For grasping a concept involves mastering the proprieties of inferential moves that connect it to many other concepts… One cannot have just one concept. This holism about concepts contrasts with the atomism that would result if one identified concepts with differential responsive dispositions (Brandom 1994, p. 89).

Brandom’s implied broad swipe here is directed towards a whole semantically formalist tradition whose origin he locates in the work of the later Frege (his reading of early Frege is considerably more commensurate with the inferentialist, expressivist and pragmatist line Brandom himself adopts). Demonstrating how sentences, and sub-sentential devices such as anaphora, primarily function to relate concepts within an inferentialist network of reasons takes Brandom much of the 741 pages of his landmark Making It Explicit (Brandom 1994). At the heart of Brandom’s enterprise is an attempt to reconcile the rigour associated with this formalist tradition with a more appropriate philosophically holistic orientation, which sees assertional speech acts within a broad tapestry of human action and ‘social practice’ generally. This has clear resonance with this particular project; although Brandom addresses neither the question of translation nor the question of knowledge systems specifically, several inferences can be drawn from his analysis:

image Knowledge systems utilise formal languages, which for Brandom differ by degree rather than kind from natural languages. A fundamental feature of a knowledge system remains that of making assertions and ‘giving reasons’. The very purpose of employing such systems, with an underlying logical apparatus, is precisely that of deriving conclusions from a set of axioms using an explicit chain of reasoning.

image More generally, the systems themselves stand as discursive practices with a general game between, typically, more course-grained sociological entities than individual actors—organisations, departments and other cultural groups.

image The semantically holistic and expressive orientation towards knowledge systems can direct attention not only towards the existing ‘knowing-thats’ asserted by the systems themselves, but also towards the background ‘knowing-hows’ and ‘knowing-thats’—the practices and as yet unexplicated conceptual commitments—of the cultures responsible for them.

image Finally, translation itself consists of a series of assertions, that concept A is synonymous with concept B, for example. The act of translation therefore entails its own ‘circumstances and consequences of application’ (to invoke another Brandom idiom). Recognition of the situational context of the translation directs attention towards just what circumstantial and consequential conditions impinge on those assertions.

A further note relates to the specific treatment of structure in Brandom’s work. The entire practice of making, interpreting and reasoning with assertions stands within what he terms an ‘I-thou deontic score-keeping’ relation. This, for Brandom, is ‘the fundamental social structure’ (Brandom 1994). This base structure operates like a simplified, idealised model, in which two interlocutors are locked into a game, metaphorically tabulating each others’ reasons offered for actions, practices, commitments, beliefs and attitudes. This theoretically endless activity does not yet offer an account for how some series of disagreements might grow into schemes which are incommensurable. To explain this—without falling prey again to Davidsonian lines of critique—requires a shift in registers, from what appears fundamentally a psychological intersubjective scenario—between two well-intentioned agents—to a sociological one—between two cultures, whose intentions are never quite irreducible to those of the agents who represent them. To make this shift the next section draws on an essential Habermasian distinction, between lifeworld and system, which offers explanation for how more fundamental rifts in the social tapestry might occur.

Socialising concepts

Where Gardenfors and Brandom acknowledge the role played by the social sphere in structuring conceptual arrangements, neither provide an account of what sorts of structure are germane to this sphere itself, nor what might cause rival conceptualisations to emerge. Kuhn and Foucault had developed explanatory theories of sorts but, at least in the case of Kuhn, these theories were limited to a particular domain of the social—the scientific domain. While no encompassing causal theory might adequately account for all variations in cultural conceptualisations—or, less abstractly, differences in how cultures see the world—a theory which at least makes perspicuous some common lines of demarcation would be helpful. Foucault’s later analysis of ‘micro-power’ goes some way in this direction, yet he consciously abjures any abstract generalisable theorisation (Foucault 1980). Bourdieu’s elaboration of ‘habitus’ is similarly useful at an intra-cultural level (Bourdieu 1990), but is not directed oriented towards an explanation of the sorts of inter-cultural differences which might arise, particularly within the ‘networked societies’ engaged in information system development and use (Castells 1996).

Habermas is sometimes taken as being either a theorist of ‘incommensurability’ (Latour 1993) or, at others, its exact opposite: a naïve advocate for an idealised ‘communicative rationality’ directed towards utopian understanding (Flyvbjerg 1998). The interpretation offered here suggests that he represents neither of these extremes, but rather a Kantian rationalism despondent—on the one hand—at the over-systematisation and objectification of modernity, yet conciliatory—on the other—towards the potentials of dialogue and communication for redressing this trend. As with the other theorists encountered here, there is insufficient scope for any kind of thorough treatment of Habermas’ full theoretical apparatus. Instead I focus attention on a pivotal conceptual opposition between system and lifeworld, outlined in The Theory of Communicative Action (Habermas 1987).

For Habermas, the Kantian trichotomy of instrumental, ethical and aesthetic rationality is ontologically primary categories of modernity. These broadly correspond to objective, inter-subjective and subjective spheres of individual experience. Habermas inherits the critical lines of Weber, Lukacs and the Frankfurt school towards post-Enlightenment reason, which has missed its potential to act as a liberating tool. Instead it has been co-opted within specifically modern configurations and systems of power and oppressive administration (Adorno 2001; Horkheimer and Adorno 2002). Rationalisation has been operationalised as an instrumental process within all spheres of human experience— everything has been subjected to systematised logic. Even individual subjectivity, what for Kant ought to remain the inviolable sanctuary of private experience, has been externalised, publicised and rendered transparent to the machinations of modern systems—through, for example, the various concrete vehicles of the media, the professed wisdoms of popular psychology, the endless commodification of art, and the cult of celebrity. For Habermas, as for critical theory, this outgrowth of hyper-rationalisation has a corresponding corrosive and pathological effect on the ‘lifeworld’—the phenomenological horizon experienced by individual subjects. Paradoxically, the domination of a singular form of rationality has also led to a fracturation and destabilisation of a social world into multiple systems. Such systems—at a macro level these include legal, economic, scientific and political systems—operate according to the internal dynamics of their particularist ends, and remain only loosely, if at all, coordinated within a social whole. Accordingly, conceptual schemes are segregated in a profound way within the system spheres in which they are engaged. Habermas describes this development:

At the level of completely differentiated validity spheres, art sheds its cultic background, just as morality and law detach themselves from their religions and metaphysical backgrounds. With this secularisation of bourgeois culture, the cultural value spheres separate off sharply from one another and develop according to the standards of the inner logics specific to the different validity claims… In the end, systemic mechanisms suppress forms of social integration even in those areas where consensus-dependent coordination of action cannot be replaced, that is, where the symbolic reproduction of the lifeworld is at stake (Habermas 1987, p. 196).

However, this historical diversion is not irrevocable within Habermas’ schema; the very conditions that effect the outgrowth of a particular form of rationalisation can also serve to corral it within its proper sphere of operation—that of scientific knowledge of the world. Provocations from the subjective sphere of experience, such as various inflections of Romanticism, are insufficient for this containment and merely serve to buttress the over-extended reach of systemic reason. Rather it is in the intersubjective sphere, where human agents engage in communication and dialogue, where reason can be directed towards not the achievement of specified functional ends, but the formation of social consensus, that functional ends can be re-evaluated within the context of society as a whole. The derivation of consensus through the pure consideration of better reasons—a never fully realised process, but nonetheless operating as a counterfactual ideal—acts as a mediating force between the private wants of subjective selves and the oppressive operations of hyper-rational systems of modernity. For Habermas communication offers the potential to arrest ‘the uncoupling of the system and lifeworld’ and return from ‘the threshold at which the mediatization of the lifeworld turns into its colonization’ (Habermas 1987).

Habermas’ analysis can be seen to supply the missing detail to Brandom’s reference to the ‘the social’, which is posited as an ‘unexplained explainer’ in his account. The connection between Habermas and Brandom is not seamless, as a recent exchange attests. Despite many points of intersection, they differ precisely over the question of whether Kantian trichotomy precedes or is instead subject to the role of logic and inference—Brandom insists, contra Habermas, that specific domains sit downstream from the primordial experience of ‘asking for and giving reasons’ (Brandom 2000b). Broadly, though, Habermas can be seen as having developed an important and encompassing explanatory account of how specific schemes can be incommensurable. In spite of how language appears, even in the work of Brandom, to be an undifferentiated tool for establishing lines of inference between co-operative agents, social systems have in the course of modernity increasingly operated according to local teleological programs, which, through the operationalisation of specific language games and jargon, serve to blunt language’s more incisive communicative potentials. Within the ‘iron cages’ of technocratic institutions, inter-system ‘interfacing’, using perfunctory rational procedures, has replaced genuine intersubjective dialogue. Within these differential ends and parametric conditions, unique morphologies of organisational cultures generate different conceptualisations of common entities. Even conceptualisations which are externalised and globalised—in the form of technology standards, for example—are typically adopted via rationalising fiat, either via conformance to de jure fiat or recognition of de facto network externalities—rather than because of an internally deliberated conclusion brought about by the force of better argument.

Unlike the accounts examined above, it is not a foregone conclusion that the conceptualisations produced within these spheres be radically incommensurable, however—only that it is possible to diagnose the potential causes, along lines of different cultural ends, procedures and intentions, when they are. Moreover the efficacy of idealised dialogue, of the kind both Habermas and Brandom are happy to countenance, and towards which actual communication constantly strives, can assuage the rougher edges of translation in practice. Brought back down to the technical domain of knowledge systems—and in lieu of any active participation between the cultures responsible for them—the role of the analyst is to ferret out both the points of differentiation and the potential conciliatory paths between them. This involves, practically, identification of salient dimensions against which such points and paths can be plotted, and a corresponding process of interrogation of the cultures responsible for the systems under review.

Habermas, then, does not endorse a romantic yearning for an overarching metaphysics, a stable social order or a single governing conceptual scheme. Nor does he champion endless devolution into more granular, localised and ultimately untranslatable systems of meaning. His aim is rather to recuperate the promise of Kantian rationality by recalibrating the obsession of modernity with instrumental reason by emphasing the equivalence of ethical and aesthetic spheres. In practice this allows systems to proliferate in their respective manifold differences, but never so far as to negate the potentials of translatability and commensurability completely. Further consideration of the greater Habermasian project would take this discussion too far afield; here it suffices to provide a sociological and historical explanation of causative factors in the incommensurability of conceptual schemes, and thus serves to connect up Brandom’s pragmatist analysis of linguistic meaning and Gardenfors’ analysis of conceptual spaces to a broad historical context. Together these connections—linking up the linguistic, the cognitive and the social—develop an altogether more fluid and elastic conception of ‘structure’, one avowedly informed by materialist and pragmatist concerns, than those advanced by the earlier generation of theorists discussed above. A path has now been prepared for the description of such a rehabilitated structure, as it relates more directly to knowledge systems and the cultures responsible for them.

Towards a framework…

The early sections of this chapter outlined three broadly commensurate positions which can be broadly subsumed under the title ‘conceptual perspectivism’. Though Foucault goes much further than Kuhn and Quine, little is articulated in these positions about why different perspectives take form—just that they do. Accordingly, these positions are all open to charges of relativism and incoherence, which Davidson and Derrida lay out powerfully. Hacking moves to outline a more nuanced position in the context of the recent ‘science wars’ of the 1990s, which demonstrates something of a dialectal force which motivates the staking out of positions and perspectives within, at least, the scientific domain. He demonstrates how the traditional debate between realism and nominalism has been resurrected in these contemporary discussions.

Habermas then supplies a more directed account—historically grounded and materialist in orientation— for how perspectives emerge and acquire currency through communicative practices. Brandom supplements this account with a more finely tuned analysis of linguistic utterances—paradigmatically, assertions—and how such utterances operate as more literal tokens within a dialogical game of ‘giving and asking for reasons’. Playing the game—requesting and making assertions—offers language users endless opportunities to revise and correct a holistic conceptual network. Gardenfors, in turn, provides a more granular account still of the kinds of things which constitute a conceptual scheme—concepts, relations and properties—within an ostensibly pragmatist framework. Together these theories can be pieced together to formulate an explanatory device for conceptual schemes which is neither relativising nor succumbs to a purely representationalist thesis—’the myth of the given’, in Sellars’ words. In short, it is possible to construct on these theoretical underpinnings a framework which embraces correspondence, coherentist and consensual notions of truth. Or, it ought now be possible to describe a framework which examines conceptual translation in terms of denotation—whether two concepts refer to the same objective things in the world; connotation—how two concepts stand in relation to other concepts and properties explicitly declared in some conceptual scheme; and use—or how two concepts are applied by their various users. Moreover there is flexibility within the framework to lean towards either ‘realism’ or ‘nominalism’, since both can be accommodated—with varying degrees of approximation—within the kind of materialist and pragmatist orientation now developed.

References

Adorno, T.W. The Culture Industry: Selected Essays on Mass Culture. Abingdon: Routledge; 2001.

Austin, J.L. How to Do Things With Words. Abingdon: Routledge; 1998.

Bourdieu, P. The Logic of Practice. Stanford: Stanford University Press; 1990.

Brandom, R. Making It Explicit. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press; 1994.

Brandom, R. Articulating Reasons: An Introduction to Inferentialism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press; 2000.

Brandom, R. Facts, Norms, and Normative Facts: A Reply to Habermas. European Journal of Philosophy. 2000; 8:356–374.

Castells, M. The Rise of the Network Society. Cambridge, MA: Blackwell; 1996.

Davidson, D. The Essential Davidson. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2006.

Derrida, J., Writing and Difference A. Bass (tr.). Routledge, Abingdon, 2001.

Flyvbjerg, B. Habermas and Foucault: Thinkers for Civil Society? British Journal of Sociology. 1998; 49:210–233.

Foucault, M. Madness and Civilization; A History of Insanity in the Age of Reason. New York: Pantheon Books; 1965.

Foucault, M. The Order of Things: An Archaeology of the Human Sciences. New York: Vintage Books; 1970.

Foucault, M., Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Writings 1972–1977. C. Gordon (tr.). Pantheon Books, New York, 1980.

Foucault, M. Archaeology of Knowledge. Abingdon: Routledge; 2002.

Gardenfors, P. Conceptual Spaces. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press; 2000.

Habermas, J., The Theory of Communicative Action T. McCarthy (tr.). Beacon Press, Boston, 1987.

Habermas, J., The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere T. Burger (tr.). MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, 1989.

Hacking, I. The Social Construction of What?. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press; 1999.

Hacking, I. Historical Ontology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press; 2002.

Horkheimer, M., Adorno, T.W., Dialectic of Enlightenment: Philosophical Fragments E. Jephcott (tr.). Stanford University Press, Stanford, 2002.

Kuhn, T.S. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press; 1970.

Kuhn, T.S., The Road Since Structure: Philosophical Essays 1970-1993with an autobiographical interview. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 2002.

Lakoff, G., Johnson, M. Metaphors We Live By. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press; 1980.

Latour, B. We Have Never Been Modern. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press; 1993.

Medin, D.L. Concepts and Conceptual Structure. American Psychologist. 1989; 44:1469–1481.

Quine, W.V.O. Word and Object. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press; 1964.

Quine, W.V.O. From a Logical Point of View. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press; 1980.

Quine, W.V.O. Interview Between W.V. Quine and Yasuhiko Tomida. http://www.wvquine.org/quine-tomida.html, 1992. [(accessed 18 January 2010)].

Pinker, S. The Language Instinct. New York: HarperCollins; 1995.

Rorty, R. Consequences of Pragmatism. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press; 1982.

Rosch, E. Cognitive Representations of Semantic Categories. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General. 1975; 104:192–233.

Sellars, W. Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press; 1997.

Wittgenstein, L. Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Mineola, IA: Dover Publications; 1921.

Wittgenstein, L. Philosophical Investigations, 3, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1967. [(first published 1953)].

..................Content has been hidden....................

You can't read the all page of ebook, please click here login for view all page.
Reset