9.3 Cofinal chains in image

9.3.1 Existence of a cofinal maximal chain of order type ω1

Definition 9.3.1. Given a partial ordering 〈P, <P〉, a set AP is a cofinal chain if the members of A are linearly ordered under P and for any zP, there is an xA such that zP x.

It is not difficult to see that under ZFC, there is a cofinal chain of Turing degrees if and only if CH holds. A natural question is whether there exists a cofinal maximal chain of order type ω1 in 〈image, ≤〉 assuming ZFC + CH. The question is considered in this section.

The following fact is immediate.

Lemma 9.3.2. Assume ZF. There exist x0 and x1 of minimal degree such that image image

Lemma 9.3.3. Assume ZF. There is a maximal chain 0 = c0 < c1 < … < cω = 0'' in [0, 0''].

Proof. Fix an enumeration (dn : nω) of degrees below 0''. Let c0 = 0.

Suppose that cn is defined with c''n = 0''. Relativize Lemma 9.3.2 to obtain degrees x0 and x1 minimal over cn such that x0x1 = c''n = 0'' = x''0 = x''1. If dn < 0'' then there is an i < 2 with image, and let cn+1 = xi. If dn = 0'', let cn+1 = x0.

Finally let cω = 0''.

Theorem 9.3.4. (Wang, Wu and Yu [168]). Assume ZFC. Then CH holds if and only if there is a cofinal maximal chain in D of order type ω1.

Proof. (⇒) Assume CH and let {dα | α < ω1} be an enumeration of the Turing degrees. We construct inductively a sequence {Cα}α<ω1 of chains such that

(1) For each β < α there is a cCα with cdβ;

(2) Cα has order type α × ω + 1 if α = 0 or is a successor ordinal;

(3) Cα has order type α × ω if α is a limit ordinal, and

(4) CβCα if β < α.

Let C0 = {0}. Suppose that α = β + 1and Cβ is defined. Given dβ, we apply Lemma 8.3.1 to obtain a minimal cover a of Cβ with a''dβ. Relativizing Lemma 9.3.3 yields a maximal chain a = a0 < a1 < … < aω = a'' in [a, a'']. Let Cα = Cβ ∪ {aγ : γ ≤ ω}. For α a limit ordinal, let image Let image It is straightforward to verify that the order type of C is ω1, C is a maximal chain, and that for each α < ω1 the (α × ω + ω + 1)-th element of C bounds dα.

(⇐) Since every degree bounds at most countably many degrees, CH follows immediately if there is a maximal chain as described.

9.3.2 CH without AC

To continue our tour of the ordering of Turing degrees, we recall some set-theoretic facts. CH is the statement that there is no set X with |ω| < |X| < |2ω|, where”|X| ≤ |Y|” means the existence of a surjective map from Y onto X. Hence ZF + CH does not obviously imply the existence of a well-ordering of reals. The same is true of GCH with regard to AC. It turns out that there is a link between these two hypotheses.

Theorem 9.3.5. (Sierpinski [136]). ZF ⊢ GCH → AC.

A question along this line is whether Theorem 9.3.5 holds level by level. For example, does CH imply the existence of a well-ordering of 2ω?

Theorem 9.3.6 (Kanamori and Pincus [62]). ZFC + “There exists an inaccessible cardinal” is consistent if and only if ZF + CH + “There is no well-ordering of 2ω” is consistent.

Proof. Assume that ZFC + “There exists an inaccessible cardinal” is consistent. By Solovay [150], there is a model M of ZF in which every uncountable set of reals contains a perfect subset. In other words, M ⊨ ZF + CH. Furthermore, there is no well-ordering of the set of reals in M.

Conversely, suppose that ZF + CH + “There is no well-ordering of 2ω” is consistent and let M be a transitive model of this theory. We claim that (ω1)M is inaccessible in L. Clearly (ω1)M is regular in L. It is sufficient to prove that for any α < (ω1)M, |(2α)L| < ω1. If not, there exists a countable α such that |(2α)L|=(ω1)M. Then (2α)LM and there is a well-ordering of (2α)L in M. Since |ω|<|(2α)L| ≤ |2ω|, we have |(2α)L|=|2ω|. In other words, there is a bijection between (2α)L and 2ω in M. It follows that there is a well-ordering of 2ω in M, which is a contradiction.

Theorem 9.3.6 says that “ZF + CH + There is no well-ordering of 2ω”is such a strong theory that an inaccessible cardinal is required to guarantee its consistency. However, for forcing extensions, one has the following:

Proposition 9.3.7. Let M ⊨ ZFC. If N is an extension of M preserving (ω1)M such that N ⊨ ZF+”There is a cofinal chain of Turing degrees”, then N ⊨ ¬CH if and only if N ⊩ “There is no well-ordering of 2ω”.

Proof. If N ⊨ “There is a well-ordering of 2ω”, then N ⊨ CH since N ⊨ ZF+”There is a cofinal chain of Turing degrees”.

Now suppose that N ⊨ “There is no well-ordering of 2ω”. Take C ∈ M to be a subset of (2ω)M such that <T is a well-ordering of C of order type (ω1)M. Since N is an extension of M preserving (ω1)M, N ⊨ |ω|<|C|. Since there is no well-ordering of 2ω in N, we have N ⊨ |C|<|2ω|. So N ⊨ ¬CH.

9.3.3 Cofinal chains versus CH

Pursuing further the link between CH and Turing degrees, one asks if, under ZF, CH is equivalent to the existence of a cofinal maximal chain of Turing degrees of order type ω1. The answer is negative: By Solovay [150], there exists a model M of ZF in which every uncountable set of reals contains a perfect subset. Since it is a theorem of ZF that every perfect set contains two reals with incomparable Turing degrees, there is no chain of Turing degrees of order type ω1.

It is not known if ZF + “There exists a cofinal maximal chain of Turing degrees of order type ω1” implies CH. However, there is a partial answer:

Theorem 9.3.8. (Wang, Wu and Yu [168]). If ZFC is consistent, then so is ZF +¬CH + “There exists a cofinal chain in the Turing degrees of order type ω1”.

The rest of this section is devoted to a proof Theorem 9.3.8. We begin with the ground model 〈L, ∈ 〉. Let ℙ be the collection of Cohen forcing conditions. ℙ1 is the resulting product forcing with finite support of length ℵ1.

For α < ω1, let ℙ<α = 〈P<α, ≤〉, where pP<α if and only if pP1 and dom(p)⊆ α. The partial order on ℙ<α is the restriction of that on ℙ1 to P<α. Thus ℙ1 =ℙ<ℵ1. Let E be the set of limit ordinals less than ω1. For α < ω1, let ωα1 be the least admissible ordinal greater than α. Then image

Lemma 9.3.9. There exist an uncountable set E1E in L and a sequence of binary relations {Rα}αE1L such that for each αE1,

RαL is a binary relation on {2n | n < ω} that is a well-ordering of order type α;

for each βα, there is a function fβT Rα which is an isomorphism between Rβ and an initial segment of Rα.

Proof. We define E1 and {Rα}αE1 by induction on α < ω1. Let E1,0 =0.Atstage α + 1, suppose that E1,α and {Rγ}γ ∈ E1,α have been defined. Let RL be a well-ordering of {22n | n < ω} of order type a limit ordinal greater than that of Rγ for γ ∈ E1,α. Then for every γ ∈ E1,α, there is a function fγ which maps Rγ isomorphically onto an initial segment of R. Let xL be a real that computes all the fγ’s. Let E1,α+1 = E1,α ∪ {γ1} where γ1 = α + ω + ω. Let R1 be a binary relation on {22n+1 | n < ω} such that for any n image (22n+1, 22m+1) ∈ R1 if and only if either nx and imagex,or nxmx and n < m. So R1T x in L and is a well-ordering of order type ω + ω on {22n+1 | n < ω}. Let

Rα+1 = RR1 ∪ {(22n, 22m+1) | n, mω}.

If α is a limit ordinal, let image and repeat the above upon replacing E1,α by E1,<α.

Let image Then E1 and {Rα}αE1 are as required.

From now on, let E1 and {Rα}αE1 in L be as above. Let G be a ℙ1-generic set over L. Then G may be viewed as an ω1-sequence {Gα}α<ω1 such that for every α < ω1, image is a real. Let G<α = {(β, Gβ) | β < α}.

Definition 9.3.10. For any γ < αE1 and any sequence {zβ}β<α of reals, define the join of {zβ}β along Rα to be the set

image

The following lemma says that the join operator is order preserving.

Lemma 9.3.11. For any β1β2α1α2E1,

image

Proof. It is immediate that Rβ2T Rα2. Let f be an Rα2-recursive function which is an isomorphism between Rβ2 and an initial segment of Rα2. Then for any n, j,

image

Hence image

The following lemma is used in the construction of a cofinal chain.

Lemma 9.3.12. For any real x and αE1, ifxL[G<α] then there is a βαinE1 such that image

Proof. Note that for any image since RαL. Suppose that xL[G<α]. There is a β1α in E such that image By Lemma 9.3.11, image Thus image Since image by relativizing Theorem 3.7.1 to image we have x to be image Hence there is a β2β1 below ω image such that image By Lemma 9.3.11 again, image Then β2 is the required β.

In L[G], if αE1 let xgα =(⊕Rα {Gγ}γ<α)(α), andlet τα be the canonical ℙ1-name of xgα. Let

image

Obviously A is a chain of Turing degrees in L[G].

Set

N =(HOD(TC({A}))L[G],

where TC({A}) ∈ L[G] is the transitive closure of {A}.

Lemma 9.3.13. For any α < ω1,

(i)<α preserves cardinals;

(ii)G<α is ℙ<α-generic over L;

(iii)A ∈ N is a cofinal chain of Turing degrees of order type ω1;

(iv)(2ω)L[G] =(2ω)N.

Proof. (i) follows from Theorem 6.1.11 and (ii) from Theorem 6.1.9, while (iv) is an immediate consequence of (iii). We prove (iii).

Given xL[G], there is an ordinal α < ω1 such that xL[G<α]. Then there is a countable ordinal α1α such that xLα1[G<α]. By Lemma 9.3.12, for any βα1 in image

Hence N is a cardinal preserving extension of L satisfying ZF+”There exists a cofinal chain of Turing degrees”. If we take N' = HOD({Gα | α < ω1}), then in N' there is no well-ordering of 2ω by the proof of Theorem 6.2.15. However, to apply the argument for N, additional precaution is required to preserve the name of A. For this purpose, we work with a subset of permutations of ω1.

If π is a permutation of ω1, let spt(π) = {α < ω1 | π(α) ≠ α}. Let H0 be the set of all permutations π of ω1 with |spt(π) | < ω, and set

H = {πH0 | (∀α < ω1)(π(α)< α + ω)}.

For each πH, let ̄ π be the permutation of L1 induced by π.

Let B be the set of ℙ1-names of reals, and define

image

Lemma 9.3.14. If image

Proof. Note that the canonical name ̌γ of γ is invariant under π, and Rγ is definable in γ as L is the minimal inner model. Then for any ℙ1-generic image differ on at most finitely many columns, the lemma follows immediately.

Corollary 9.3.15. If πH, then image

Hence the permutations in H are sufficient to show

N ⊨ “There is no well-ordering of 2ω”.

By Proposition 9.3.7, N ⊨ ¬CH and this completes the proof of Theorem 9.3.8.

9.3.4 Exercises

Exercise 9.3.1. Prove Lemma 9.3.2.

Exercise 9.3.2. (Kunen). Prove that if there is a well-ordering of the Turing degrees, then there is a well-ordering of 2ω.

Exercise 9.3.3. (Wang, Wu and Yu [168]). Prove that in the proof of Theorem 9.3.8, we may assume M ⊨ ZFC + CH + ω1 =(ω1)L.

Exercise 9.3.4. Prove that there is a model M of ZF in which no set of reals has exactly one representative from each Turing degree, and in which there is a thin set A where 2ω A is also thin.

9.4 ω-homogeneity of the Turing degrees

Definition 9.4.1.image, ≤〉 is ω-homogeneous if for any two n + 1-tuples (a0,…, an) and (b0, …, bn) in image, if 〈image, ≤, a0,…, an〉 ≡ 〈image, ≤, b0,…, bn〉 then there is an automorphism π : imageimage such that π(ai) = π(bi) for each in.

Slaman and Woodin [144] showed:

Theorem 9.4.2. The ω-homogeneity of image, ≤〉 is independent of ZFC.

We say that a function f : 2ω → 2ω presents an automorphism π : 〈image, ≤〉 → 〈image, ≤〉 if for every Turing degree x and real xx, f(x) ∈ π(x). The next two results are needed for Theorem 9.4.2 and are stated without proof.

Theorem 9.4.3. Every automorphism π : 〈image, ≤〉 → 〈image, ≤〉 is presented by an arithmetical function f :2ω → 2ω.

If R is a degree invariant relation over (2ω)n+1 for some n, then it induces a relation on degrees such that image xnxn ∧ (x0,…, xn) ∈ R). We identify with R for simplicity.

Theorem 9.4.4. For any relation R over D which is induced by a degree invariant analytical relation over 2ω, if R is invariant under any automorphism of D, then R is definable in 〈image, ≤〉.

We now prove Theorem 9.4.2.

Lemma 9.4.5. If V = L, thenimage, ≤〉 is ω-homogeneous.

Proof. By Proposition 4.4.2, <L is a image well-ordering of 2ω. The lexicographic ordering of n + 1-tuples induced by <L implies that for each n there is a image well-ordering <n+1 of (2ω)n+1.

For m < ω and kn, let Rm,k ⊆ (2ω)n+1 be such that

(x0,…, xn) ∈ Rm,kkn

(∃y0)…(∃yn)((y0,…, yn) is the <n+1 -least so that

(∃π)(∀in)(π : 〈image, ≤〉 → 〈image, ≤〉 is an automorphism ∧ π(yi) = ximyk)).

It is straightforward to verify that Rm,k is degree invariant and hence induces a relation on image invariant under any automorphism. By Theorem 9.4.3, Rm,k is also analytical. Hence by Theorem 9.4.4, Rm,k is definable in 〈image, ≤〉.

Suppose that 〈image, ≤, a0,…, an〉≡〈image, ≤, b0,…, bn〉. Then Rm,k (a0,…, an)⇔ Rm,k(b0,…, bn) for every m and kn. For such a k, define yk so that myk if and only if Rm,k(a0,…, an). By the definition of Rm,k, there are automorphisms π0 and π1 such that for every kn, π0(yk) = ak and π1(yk) = bk. Then π1π−10 is an automorphism between 〈image, ≤〉 and 〈image, ≤〉, and π1π−10(ak) = bk, implying that 〈image, ≤〉 is ω-homogeneous.

We complete the proof of Theorem 9.4.2 with the following lemma.

Lemma 9.4.6. If V = L[g] where g is a Cohen generic real, thenimage, ≤〉 is not ω-homogeneous.

Proof. Let g = g0g1. We leave it to the reader to verify that (g0, g1) is a pair of generic reals over a product Cohen forcing ℂ×ℂ. Then by Theorem 9.4.3, there is no automorphism of 〈image, ≤〉 sending g0 to g1.

Now let φ be a formula such that 〈L[g], ∈ 〉 = 〈L[(g0, g1)], ∈ 〉 ⊨ “〈image, ≤〉 ⊨ φ(g0)”. Then there is a condition (p0, p1) ∈ 2<ω × 2<ω such that |p0|=|p1|, (p0, p1)≺(g0, g1) and image Obviously there is an automorphism π : ℂ×ℂ → ℂ×ℂ so that π((p0, p1)) =(p1, p0) and π(ġ0) =ġ1. By Proposition 6.1.17, (p1, p0) ⊩ “〈 ̇ image, ̇ ≤〉 ⊨ φ( ̇ g1)”. Then 〈L[(g1, g0)], ∈ 〉 ⊨ “〈image, ≤〉 ⊨ φ(g1)”. However, L[(g1, g0)] = L[(g0, g1)] = L[g] and thus 〈L[g], ∈ 〉 ⊨ “〈image, ≤〉 ⊨ φ(g1)”. Hence 〈image, ≤〉 is not ω-homogeneous.

9.5 Some general independence results

For a general reference on the subject of Turing degrees, see Lerman [82]. Let L ( ≤ ) be the language of partial ordering. L ( ≤ ) is a set definable in the language of set theory. Furthermore, both 〈image, ≤〉 and the relation “〈image, ≤〉 ⊨ φ” may be viewed as definable sets in the language of set theory. We code each formula φ in L ( ≤ ) by a number ⌜φ⌝. Let

Th∃2image, ≤〉 = {⌜φ⌝| φ is a Σ2-sentence in L ( ≤ ) ∧ 〈image, ≤〉 ⊨ φ}.

Lerman and Shore [131] proved:

Theorem 9.5.1. The set Th∃2(image, ≤ ) is recursive.

Hence the set Th∃2image, ≤〉 is definable by a image-formula ψ0 and a image-formula ψ1. It follows that for any Σ2-sentence φ,

ZFC ⊢ “〈image, ≤〉 ⊨ φψ0(⌜φ⌝)”

and

ZFC ⊢ “〈image, ≤〉 ⊨ ¬φ ⇔¬ψ1(⌜φ⌝)”.

Since for any image-formula ψ(u) and natural number n,

ZFC ⊢ ψ(n)⇔〈ω, ≤, +, ⋅,0,1〉 ⊩ ψ(n),

(see [145]), for any Σ2-sentence φ either

ZFC ⊢ “〈image, ≤〉 ⊨ φ

or

ZFC ⊢ “〈image, ≤〉) ⊨ ¬φ”.

Hence we have the following conclusion.

Corollary 9.5.2. For any Σ2-sentence φ in L ( ≤ ),either”image, ≤〉 ⊨ φ” or “image, ≤〉 ⊨ ¬φ” is provable in ZFC.

Clearly the set Pr = {⌜φ⌝| ZFC ⊢ “〈image, ≤〉 ⊨ φ”} is r. E. The complexity of the theory of the Turing degrees was established by Simpson [139]:

Theorem 9.5.3. ZFC proves that there is a recursive bijection f : ωω such that for any n, n ∈ {⌜φ⌝|〈image, ≤〉 ⊨ φ} if and only if f(n) ∈ {⌜ψ⌝|〈ω, 2ω, +, ⋅, ≤, ∈ 〉 ⊨ ψ}, where ψ is a formula in the language of second order arithmetic.

Thus ZFC proves that the set {⌜φ⌝|〈image, ≤〉 ⊨ φ} is not analytical. It follows that for any M ⊨ ZFC, we have Pr ⊂ {⌜φ⌝| M ⊨ “〈image, ≤〉 ⊨ φ”}. This leads to the following conclusion.

Corollary 9.5.4. For any M ⊨ ZFC, there is a sentence φ such thatφ⌝ ∈ {⌜ψ⌝| “〈image, ≤〉 ⊨ ψ”} Pr.

Let M ⊨ ZFC and φ be as above. Since ZFC ⊬ “〈image, ≤〉 ⊨ φ”, there exists a model N ⊨ ZFC such that N ⊨ “〈image, ≤〉 ⊨ ¬φ”. Hence the statement “〈image, ≤〉 ⊨ φ” is independent of ZFC. This argument implies the existence of a sentence φ not provable in ZFC, but does not provide any information about φ. The following offers more information: By Corollary 4.4.1, the statement “every real is constructible” is image Hence there is a sentence φ in L ( ≤ ) such that 〈image, ≤〉 ⊨ φ if and only if every real is constructible. Thus the statement “〈image, ≤〉 ⊨ φ” is independent of ZFC. However, a weakness in the argument is that the sentence φ is highly complicated, not necessarily considered “natural”, and heavily dependent on the coding scheme. It is not known if there is a “natural” sentence in image that is independent of ZFC.

..................Content has been hidden....................

You can't read the all page of ebook, please click here login for view all page.
Reset